For William James (1842-1910), all philosophical problems were ultimately ethical. In Pragmatism (1907), James invoked the logical theory of his friend Charles Peirce to argue the of any belief consisted solely in conduct it is fitted to produce. There difference in abstract he elaborated, that doesn't express itself in a difference in concrete fact and in conduct consequent upon fact, imposed on somebody, somehow, somewhere, and somewhen. Indeed, James concluded truth not reflected in the consequences of conduct but shaped by them: Truth is he wrote, just as health, wealth, and strength are made, in the course of experience.1 This major thesis of Pragmatism distilled a career spent describing an unfinished world, in which human thoughts and actions made differences for which thinkers and actors were responsible. As early as 1878, James insisted beliefs imply to advance goals, creating effects valued in light of those goals. mind, he reiterated in his 1890 masterpiece Principles of Psychology, is a fighter for ends, and thinking, a act. Later, in The Will to Believe (1896), James argued when evidence is inconclusive, belief might create conditions in which hypotheses could be verified and potential goods realized - or lost. That frank (if often overlooked) assessment of the moral risks as well as rewards of intellectual life echoed James's most explicitly ethical work, The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life (1891), where he asserted when choosing what to believe, it is simply our total character and personal genius are on trial; and if we invoke any so-called philosophy, our choice and use of also are but revelations of our personal aptitude or incapacity for moral life.2In short, James, as John Dewey elegized in 1910, was everywhere and always the moralist.3 Yet for much of the twentieth century critics deemed James's philosophy ethically vacuous, a warrant for moral solipsism. In 1909, Bertrand Russell criticized James for privileging belief over suspension of judgment, and thus encouraging people to live in private moral universes rather than seek objective grounding for common values. Today, some intellectual historians continue to echo Russell and likeminded contemporaries, judging ethical pragmatism tantamount to moral relativism, even moral apathy.4 Others, acknowledging James's impassioned pronouncements on lynching, industrial conflict, imperialist expansion, and other public moral issues, have interpreted them as expressing a particularly cosmopolitan but otherwise unremarkable American liberalism, rather than a coherent moral philosophy.5These criticisms are unfounded, but understandable. They reflect a general antipathy toward James's broader conceptions of knowledge, truth, and experience, and frustration with his unorthodox mode of philosophizing. In Pragmatism, James followed Peirce in arguing beliefs are not copies of reality, but rules for action resembling the probabilistic predictions guiding scientific inquiry. James, however, extended Peirce's argument, claiming there is no static reality beliefs can once-for-all describe. A self-proclaimed radical empiricist, James held the universe is pluralistic, and the only reality accessible to human minds is constantly changing - not least through the ceaseless flux of human consciousness, a fact as natural and consequential as any other.6 This blurring of subject-object distinctions scandalized contemporaries. It also underpinned James's equally scandalous claim ideas not only demonstrate their meaning through conduct, but derive both meaning and value from their origins and verification in human activity. To ask what is true in such a world to ask which ideas, moral or otherwise, allow people to navigate it successfully - which carry us prosperously from any one of our experience to any other part - and which do not. …
Read full abstract