MLRy 100.3, 2??5 785 implicitly critical of the 'tendency of economic analysis to abstain from [. . .] moral evaluation' (p. 232), and one of the strengths of the book is its alertness to the ethical issues raised by the texts under discussion. King's College London Warren Chernaik Sterne, theModerns, and theNovel. By Thomas Keymer. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2002. xiv + 222pp. ?47. ISBN 0-19-924592-4. Scepticism and Literature: An Essay on Pope, Hume, Sterne, and Johnson. By Fred Parker. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2003. x + 290pp. ?50. ISBN o19 -925328-8. Both Thomas Keymer and Fred Parker have written 'source studies', though their books have little in common besides a reading of Laurence Sterne. Parker's Scepticism and Literature proves true to its subtitle by emulating the loosely discursive nature of the traditional essay form. Parker writes a thoroughly untheoretical ifnot unsystematic study of 'sceptical thinking' in four eighteenth-century authors, whose models are Montaigne and Locke. In Sterne, theModerns, and theNovel Thomas Keymer draws upon theories of intertextuality in order to argue that Tristram Shandy is very much a part of the popular literary,political, and social culture of its own day. Parker's study is focused on what Keymer calls 'positivist claims about "influence"' (p. 11), while Keymer explores the 'hypotexts' or 'aleatory' networks of influence and allusion. Even though Keymer's study is more narrowly focused than Parker's (one genre, one author, one novel), his historicist approach produces more general knowledge about eighteenth-century culture than Parker's does. Parker's study of scepticism features much finewriting about Locke, Pope, Hume, Sterne, and Johnson. Working through close readings of major texts, Parker argues that Locke's epistemology limits the quest for general truths and that Montaigne's Essays instruct his readers to 'live according to nature' (p. 39) by enacting the author's 'intellectual helplessness' (p. 37). Parker trains a keen eye on the 'paradox of irony' in his four authors to show their debts to Locke and Montaigne and to argue that 'scepti? cism generates understanding' (p. 30), by which he means practical knowledge rather than rational certainty. In some of these authors this practical knowledge seems very near a sentiment from Rochester's Satyr: 'Our Sphere of Action, is lifes happiness, | And he who thinks Beyond, thinks like an Ass.' If their practical knowledge never becomes the foundation for the Epicurean creed found in Rochester, it is thanks to either religion or the age's refinement. Parker's readings portray a group of authors who take their motto fromthe opening of Epistle II of Pope's Essay on Man: 'With too much knowledge forthe Sceptic side, | With too much weakness forthe Stoic's pride | [They] hang between' rationalism and scepticism, ideation and experience, stability and flux,philosophy and backgammon, solipsism and sociality, system and spontaneity, conclusiveness and doubt. Rather than let 'dull Suspense corrupt the stagnant mind', they embrace a dynamic commit? ment to thought. When thinking does not provide them with intellectual comfort, they have recourse to other solutions. Hume's answer to the pain of doubt is 'estab? lished custom and convention, [. . .] the eighteenth-century game of polite society' (p. 163). When Pope is not resting comfortably with fideism in his Essay ('Hope humbly then; with trembling pinions soar; | Wait the great teacher Death, and God adore!'), he is taking pleasure in flapping a degenerate society's darlings. Sterne, as has long been noted, takes his pleasure in the ambiguous gesture, in the hand that reaches out in the darkness to find a friend or define an end. In Johnson, Parker finds a need for certainty, a 'horror at finality' (p. 240), and 786 Reviews a 'stressful moral urgency' (p. 248) that distinguishes him from the other writers of the study. As Parker reads through the Idler and Rasselas, however, he argues that Johnson finds his relief in 'open-endedness [. . .] an ironic understanding of the moralist and the sceptic as in necessary, perpetual dialogue' (p. 266). In his drive to reach conclusions about hanging between scepticism and stoicism, Parker underestimates the psychological cost of finding existential solutions to the feltneed for certainty, and thus underestimates the intensity of Johnson...
Read full abstract