Bioregionalism can strengthen environmental pragmatism by making it more critical of the status quo and even more environmental, without abandoning pragmatism's democratic aims. It thus answers important objections to pragmatism raised by Robyn Eckersley. Despite some apparent differences, bioregionalism is a form of environmental pragmatism, as it incorporates practical ethics and is committed to pluralism and democratic community. Bryan Norton's environmental pragmatism is already close to a bioregional view. After answering Eckersley, the paper concludes by raising the question of whether environmental pragmatists should be bioregionalists.Robin Eckersley criticizes environmental pragmatism for not being sufficiently radical or even sufficiently environmental.1 This is due, she says, to its role as a mediator rather than an advocate in environmental issues, a role that weakens environmental pragmatism's democratic credentials because it is fails to empower marginalized groups and interests. Eckersley' s criticisms should not be ignored. On the other hand, bioregionalism, or a bioregional environmental pragmatism, is not limited in the ways that Eckersley identifies. It can take a stronger environmentalist position while maintaining a commitment to pragmatism's mediator role. Despite bioregionalism' s and environmental pragmatism's different histories - one a grass roots movement, the other a more academic movement - they have several important things in common. Both emphasize practical rather than theoretical concerns, and see theory as a tool for accomplishing concrete ends; both focus on local action by local communities; both value pluralism. Admittedly, bioregionalists do not usually refer to themselves as pragmatists, and many hold some non-naturalist views at odds with pragmatic naturalism. Nonetheless, I will argue that in terms of its core values, bioregionalism is actually a form of environmental pragmatism. More to the point, I will argue that bioregionalism can address Eckersley' s criticisms while advancing pragmatism's goal of enhancing public participation.The present paper first outlines the main ideas of bioregionalism. It then argues that bioregionalism - especially its ethics of reinhabition - is fundamentally a kind of practical ethics, which makes it a form of pragmatism. Next, discussion turns to two central commitments of environmental pragmatism - pluralism and democratic community. Bioregionalism grounds these commitments in local life -places. We will see that Bryan Norton's pragmatism, which emphasizes place-based community, is already close to a bioregional view. Finally, we will see how bioregionalism can overcome Eckersley's objections that environmental pragmatism is insufficiently radical or environmental. The paper concludes by asking whether environmental pragmatists should, then, be bioregionalists.1. Bioregionalism and the Ethics of ReinhabitationBecause it is highly decentralized, both as a movement and a body of thought, a precise definition of bioregionalism is hard to come by. This may be for the best in a practiced-based and constantly evolving cultural movement. Better, says bioregionalist writer Jim Dodge, that definitions emerge from practice than be imposed dogmatically on the movement. This is an admirable pragmatist sentiment. Despite lacking a clear definition, it is clear that bioregionalism is primarily concerned with the ecological health of local life -places and with sustainable ways of living that are adapted to those places. Bioregionalists may take on wider problems that affect other regions and the planet as a whole, but the starting place of concern is local.A bioregion, etymologically, is a life -place. Normally we might define a region politically, economically, ethnically, or some other exclusively human activity. In contrast, a ?ioregion is marked out in terms of biotic communities, watersheds and terrain. Or it may be defined by a few dominant species, by a mountain range, a drainage system, or any number of natural features. …
Read full abstract