Justice Potter Stewart: The Unpredictable Vote Gayle Binion At the time of his appointment to the United States Supreme Court in 1958,’ Potter Stewart was asked to describe hisjudicial philosophy. He responded, “I like to be thought ofas a lawyer.”2 In a personal interview, eighteen years later, he reiterated this preference.3 When he announced his retirement in 1981, he told reporters he hoped he would be remembered “as a good lawyer who did his best.” Stewart was especially concerned he not be labeled as either a liberal or a conserva tive, labels readily attached to the Justices with whom he served.4 To Stewart, those labels sug gested a Justice who acted upon his own ecoPotter Stewart relaxing at home. Stewart served as an Associate Justice from 1958-1981. He strived to be remembered “as a good lawyer who did his best” throughout his career. nomic, political, social, or religious values. In contrast, his Justice-as-lawyer role model sug gested for him ajurist capable ofapplying objec tive legal reasoning to questions before the Court, uninfluenced by his own values. Although Stew art was fully aware of the enormous social, eco nomic and political consequences which Court de cisionsmayhave,hecontinuedtobelieve one could, nevertheless, set aside one’s own philosophical values as bases for decision making.5 It appears, even at the close ofhis career on the Court, Stewart had succeeded in eluding the pigeon-holers.6 The most commonly used terms to describe Stewart: “moderate,”7 “neutral,”8 and“swingvoter,”9 reflect his tendency to vote “liberal” in some cases and “conservative” in others, and his propensity to defy prediction in specific cases. Constitutional scholars, often frustratedin theirattemptto pinpoint Stewart’s ideology,havetendedto ignorehisroleon the Court,haveassumedhis positionsweretheresult ofinconsistent or random decision making, or have attempted to assess his votes along an ideological continuum as definedby allianceswithbrethren.10 Careful analysis of Stewart’s decisions, however, reveals therewere significantpredictors ofhis posi tions on the controversial issues ofhis day, but they were not necessarily inherent in thesubstance of the legalquestionsbeforetheCourt. Primaryamong his values, and explanatory ofmany ofhis allegedly unpredictable votes, were his fervent commitment to states’ rights and an equally strong commitment to narrow, non-anticipatory decision making. It is thislatterorientationwhichcontributestohislawyerly self-image, but it is the former which rationalizes 100 JOURNAL 1992 many ofhis otherwise incomprehensible decisions. States’ Rights Federalism The most significantelement in Stewart’sjuris prudence was his commitment to states’ rights. To most students ofconstitutional law, states’ rights is a relic of our darkest past, a constitutionalism that supported slavery, corporate oligopoly, and the in ability ofthe federal governmentto deal with twen tieth-centuryproblems. The ideologyofdual feder alism, under which the Tenth Amendment stood as a positive restriction on national authority, was laid to rest in U.S. v. Darby Lumber" in 1941, when Justice Harlan Stone proclaimed “the [Tenth] Amendment states but a truism that all is retained [bythe states] whichhas notbeen surrendered.” But Stewart, in contrast with the predominant legal thought ofour age, and with the Supreme Court on which he served, maintained a commitmentto dual federalism, to the belief that states continued to retainsubstantial constitutionalautonomy. Dissent ing alone in Perez v. U.S.12 in 1971, he concluded Justice Stewart dissented in Perez v. United States (1971), arguing that loan-sharking was only a local practice. Frank Tieri, above, is shown after his arrest by the FBI in New York on federal loan sharking charges. that loan-sharking was only a local business prac tice, and, therefore, despite its occurrence nation wide, not subject to congressional regulation. His Tenth Amendment reasoning was reminiscent of ideas largely abandoned by the Court duringthe era of Franklin D. Roosevelt. Stewart also dissented againstguaranteeingto defendants in state criminal proceedings the pro tections contained in the Bill of Rights.13 He viewed the imposition ofthese restrictions on the states as an interference with their conduct oftheir criminaljustice systems. Because the operation of a criminaljustice system was, for Stewart, an essen tialfunctionofgovemment, largely definitionalof a sovereign state, he was extremely unlikely to favor abridging the autonomy ofthe states in this area. His votes in Malloy v. Hogan" Benton v. Maryland," and Duncan v. Louisiana" against the “incorporation” of, respectively, the...
Read full abstract