In reviewing John Dunn on Modern Revolutions and myself on Social Order , Reform , and Revolution, ( Sociology , 7: 1, Jan. 1973, pp. 149-50) Michael Mann applauds Dunn's book and suggests that Dunn is only kidding in his critical remarks on the sociology of revolution. On reading his review of my own book, my initial impression was that Mann must be kidding too. On re-reading it, however, I gathered that Mann was actually serious in his remarks. No author should mind if a reviewer expresses dislike of his work but the reasons for such dislike should not misrepresent the author nor be untenable. As Mann's review does misrepresent my views, I would be grateful for space to reply to his criticisms. (1) Mann summarizes my basic argument as 'reform and revolution are different ways in which the periphery can take advantage of contradictions between (i) different subsystems and (ii) forces and relations of production in any subsystem, to act against the centre and reduce the rate of exploitation'. In the very first chapter, however, reform and revolution are distinguished in terms of their relative institutionalization rather than in terms of their protagonists and it is argued that, in a structurally differentiated society, revolution can be implemented by one or more power centres. Secondly, although they obviously play an important part in more radical social changes (whether reforms or revolution), I do not see contradictions as the only source of change. (2) Mann then proceeds to quote me out of context to the effect that normative order is the key factor in historical materialism. The quotation actually has as referent only Gramsci whose views I earlier allude to as being distinctive, and not Lenin, Marx, or Engels. I also emphasize throughout the discussion of classical Marxism that the economic base is there seen as the primary force in societal dynamics. This misquote has a function, however, since it enables Mann to make a joke about Hegel being turned on his feet again the same joke as has often been made about Gramsci, whose views I was describing, and Lukacs. It is true that I argue that normative factors (which are not to be equated with the superstructure a residual phenomenon) are important in Marxist theory, particularly when it comes to explain social order rather than impending revolution, but I also point out the important differences in this and other respects from functionalism. (3) I am then reproached with the failure, having mentioned Althusser and Granisci, to develop or probe the relations between the economic base and superstructure and the manner in which economic factors are determinant in the last instance. As Mann himself argues in his recent monograph on working class consciousness, Althusser is concerned to establish a multicausal approach to structural dynamics and can be read as showing how the last resort may never arrive owing to an earlier ruptural overdetermination of various contradictions. Gramsci goes further and treats the superstructure as the key factor. Given all this, along with the ambiguity of the base-superstructure distinction, my own argument that the different power systems are irreducible to each other, my concern with all societies and not just those capitalist societies in which the economic centre is dominant, and my belief that the forces/ relations of production concept can be generalized, it would seem that, in developing a multicausal approach, I am in fact following one possible line of development from Althusser albeit not that which Mann prescribes. (4) Later in his review, Mann holds that my use of 'cultural power' to include control over every type of value, belief, or socially derived meaning is vacuous. He also finds it odd that I relate culture to the relations of production. Having been reproached earlier for being insufficiently Althusserian, I suppose one must take pleasure in being more Althusserian than Mann in
Read full abstract