'I am not speaking' is a truth I cannot speak. Similarly, when T am not thinking' is true, I cannot think it without rendering it false. But consider a world where eliminativism obtains, where no one can strictly speak or think of anything at all. In that world, are there that I* (my counterpart) cannot speak or think? The answer may seem trivially yes, since I* cannot speak or think anything. But suppose, as is plausible, that truths are representational items, meaningful sentences or thoughts. Then the answer is no. For there would be no truths, hence no unspeakable or unthinkable truths. Though there would still be facts of which I* cannot speak or think.In particular, I* would be unable to speak or think of the very fact I* cannot speak or think. Suppose I* nonetheless utter the sounds 'I am not speaking or thinking'. Imagine, moreover, that my* cohorts are behaviorally conditioned to respond with 'That's false, since you say that you are not speaking, yet you are speaking when you say that.' Still, in an eliminativist world, these things are meaningless, so none of it would be true or false.But suppose we project the English onto my* utterance 'I am not speaking or thinking.' Under that pretense, my* utterance would then be false. For according to that pretense, I* am indeed speaking. So if we impose the that my* utterance has its English meaning, then I* speak falsely in uttering 'I* cannot speak or think anything'-even though I* cannot speak or think anything!Eliminativism is often said to be self-refuting, much in the manner of 'I am not speaking'. But eliminativism may be self-refuting only if we adopt the meaning pretense. And if eliminativism is false under that pretense, it does not follow that it is false. Or rather, it still could be a fact. My aim is to make all this clearer, but in doing so, I do not mean to endorse eliminativism. My aim is instead to show merely that certain objections against eliminativism are nondemonstrative, once the very idea of selfrefutation is seen as part of a pretense.Nonetheless, there is a price incurred by such pretense-theoretic eliminativism or fictionalism. The mental fictionalist must reject the language of mental fictionalism, and will be forced into a kind of quietism.1. What is Mental Fictionalism?Fictionalism, broadly speaking, is a nonrealist stance toward ontologically suspicious entities (numbers, possible worlds, morals, etc.). However, beyond the differences in entities, there is still a surprising variety among views that are called fictionalist. (For a general overview, see Kalderon 2005a; Eklund 2011; Kroon 2011.) Many apply the label 'fictionalist' even to van Fraassen's (1980) view of scientific unobservables. That is so, even though van Fraassen does not describe unobservables as fictions; he is rather agnostic about their existence.1Even among nonagnostic factionalisms, there are further key differences. Thus, Field's regards mathematical discourse as literally false (even though mathematics remains a rational activity, insofar as it is useful). In contrast, a modal fictionalist (cf. Rosen 1990; Nolan 1997; 2002) regards some modal statements as literally true despite the rejection of possible worlds.2 This is done by interpreting, e.g., 'I might have been a dentist' as saying that According to the fiction, there is a possible world where I became a dentist. (The fiction here is an unflattering reference to [the closure of] Lewis's Modal Realism; see Lewis 1968; 1973; 1986.) Importantly, it is literally true that there is such a world according to Lewis s view. Yet Lewis's view is seen as mere fiction; so the modal fictionalist is still able to deny that such a world exists.3The view I call fictionalism is modeled more after modal fictionalism.4 Roughly, it adopts the modal fictionalist's stance toward mentalistic discourse (i.e. …