EVEN AT ITS CONCEPTION AND ITS VERY FIRST ARTICULATION IN THE critique Judgment, Kant's aesthetic theory may be seen as problematic. undeniable and unyielding contrast between and in particular, only turns second half analytic aesthetic into what Paul de Man calls most difficult and unresolved passages in entire corpus [his] works (1) but also compels Kant to dismiss notion sublime right inside his own discussion as not nearly so important or rich in consequences as concept beautiful or as mere appendix to aesthetical judging that purposiveness. (2) Yet urge to exclude sublime from Kant's aesthetic theory and to malign it as of [not] much interest to modern sensibilities (3) surely as unimaginative as attempt to promote sublime unilaterally and to vilify as outmoded--passe even. (4) In order to salvage Kant's insights and rebuild them into what Paul Crowther terms more general theory aesthetic judgment (139), what so necessary and important to see and appreciate only how there a complex relationship both similarities and differences between and sublime but also how such a relationship between them makes it possible for them to work out as Kant's paradise lost and paradise regained. No matter how sublime may differ from beautiful, two them nevertheless resemble each other at same time. Even though Kant touches upon former only after he completes analysis latter, only he therefore launching into something that fundamentally different from what he has till then called a taste but he also in a very real sense talking about same thing. The and sublime, as he says, agree in this that both please in themselves (Critique Judgment #23, 82). Taking place only during a cognitive interaction between a subject and an object but setting itself apart from both a sense and a logical determination, sublime as much a reflection as beautiful. As such, it analogously both similar to and different from pleasant and good. Like pleasant, for instance, sublime a singular experience, but unlike pleasant, it does derive its satisfaction from any current and therefore transient need for any particular object. Like good, on other sublime makes a universal claim for its judgment, but unlike good, at same time it separates validation such a collective contention from any ideas either utility or ultimate purpose. Totally disinterested and centrally concerned only with what Kant terms the mere [of object] or the faculty presentation (#23, 82), sublime as much about internal relationship man's cognitive capabilities as beautiful. In spite all their similarities, however, and sublime are nevertheless set apart from one another by their concurrent differences. The in nature connected with form as Kant points out, which consists in having [definite] boundaries (#23, 82). The on other hand, as he goes on to say, is to be found in a formless object, so far as in it or by occasion it boundlessness represented, and yet its totality also present to thought (#23, 82). Connected with the representation quality and the an indefinite concept understanding, pleasure directly brings with it a feeling furtherance life, and thus compatible with charms and with play imagination (#23, 82, 83). Bound up with representation quantity and an indefinite concept reason, satisfaction sublime instead pleasure that arises only indirectly; viz. …
Read full abstract