ly. He may have done so by promoting a contrary practice (his theistic practice of science) as if it represented the logical contradictory of dogmatic naturalism: assuming that, if, for the dogmatic naturalist, scientific claims precluded the theistic one, then, for nondogmatic naturalism, scientific claims must include them. Otherwise put, Peirce believed that the scientist must acknowlege God as author of our universes of experience, but, as yet, he lacked any nondogmatic means of demonstrating that his belief was true. The dialectic of pragmatic critique and unpragmatic dogma was 16 Susan Haack, Descartes, Peirce and the Cognitive Community, in The Relevance of Charles Peirce, ed. Eugene Freeman (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1983), p. 254. 17 From an unpublished sequel to Peirce's 1866 Lowell Lectures (MS 359), cited in Orange, pp. 21-22. For future reference, MS refers to Peirce's unpublished manuscripts as they appear in The Charles S. Peirce Papers (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Library, Photographic Service, 1966). The manuscripts are numbered according to the system of Richard S. Robin, Annotated Catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1967). 18 As argued in an unpublished critique of positivism (MS 970, 1867-68), cited in Orange, pp. 17-18. 19 MS 354, cited in Orange, pp. 9-20.
Read full abstract