Aristotle and Newman on the Concreteness of Theoretical Knowing Jonathan Buttaci* "Aristotle has been my master."1 In The Idea of a University John Henry Newman affirmed the inevitable influence—overt or covert—of Aristotle on our thinking. He wrote: While the world lasts, will Aristotle's doctrine on these matters last, for he is the oracle of nature and of truth. While we are men, we cannot help, to a great extent, being Aristotelians, for the great Master does but analyze the thoughts, feelings, views, and opinions of human kind. He has told us the meaning of our own words and ideas, before we were born. In many subject-matters, to think correctly, is to think like Aristotle; and we are his disciples whether we will or no, though we may not know it.2 This approach, in general, motivates the present article, reflecting on Aristotelian themes in Newman's thought and, in turn, exploring how he might aid the scholar of Aristotle. I argue that, at least in one crucial respect, Newman's thought is even more thoroughly Aristotelian than has been appreciated. [End Page 56] More specifically, this paper begins with an insight animating Newman's thought throughout his life and its potential tension with Aristotle. Newman wrote (and reiterated), "After all, man is not a reasoning animal; he is a seeing, feeling, contemplating, acting animal. He is influenced by what is direct and precise."3 This remark may be taken to be un-Aristotelian or even anti-Aristotelian in spirit, and on at least two counts. First, Aristotle and those working in the Aristotelian tradition commonly regard man as a rational and reasoning animal, indeed, defining him as such.4 Second, for Aristotle the characteristic human activity is theoretical or contemplative activity most of all. If that means trading in what is abstract and universal, as is commonly held, then by saying "[man] is influenced by what is direct and precise," Newman would have been proposing a substantial revision of Aristotelian views of theoretical knowledge, even while acknowledging an enormous debt to Aristotle's practical philosophy.5 So goes one interpretation of Newman's work based on a certain understanding of Aristotle's theory.6 According to this interpretation, in emphasizing concrete particulars and "what is direct and precise," Newman thereby thought "practice controls theory,"7 reversing the Aristotelian priority of theoretical knowing. If this were the right view, although Aristotle had been his master in general, Newman would have departed from Aristotle on this point by prioritizing the concrete, practical, and imaginative, and by subordinating the abstract, theoretical, and intellectual.8 [End Page 57] In this article I argue against that interpretation. Instead, Newman was more Aristotelian than it may seem, at least on this issue.9 Far from being un- or anti-Aristotelian, Newman's insistence that we are not merely syllogizing animals, and that even our theoretical knowledge is rooted in and directed toward concrete particulars, is thoroughly at home within Aristotle's thought. In fact, careful attention to Aristotle's scientific works shows the importance of familiarity with concrete particulars, as both the origin and the end of theoretical knowing. When these passages are read with Newman's chief philosophical insights in mind, they correct a common misreading of Aristotle, in fact, the very misreading that generates the alleged tension between Newman and Aristotle on this issue. As we shall see, Aristotle did not favor abstractions while rendering concrete experience superfluous or merely preparatory. On the contrary, even in Aristotle's account of theoretical knowing, the abstract is subordinated to the concrete. This way of reading Aristotle helps us to appreciate an even greater harmony between them.10 PRACTICAL LOGOS, INCARNATE AND EMPTY Before examining Newman's alleged departure from Aristotle when it comes to theoretical knowing, I begin with one strand of Newman's thinking that is uncontroversially Aristotelian. My eventual aim is to see how these uncontroversial Aristotelian debts in the practical case reveal deeper connections in their accounts of theoretical knowing. [End Page 58] Let us begin with a quote from Newman's sermon "On Holiness."11 Each of the following passages reveals the broadly Aristotelian view about human...
Read full abstract