In the paper to which Saladin Meckled-Garcia has responded so thoughtfully, I proposed that rights should be viewed not as moral claims, but as effectively enforceable claims that make a practical difference to people's lives. When an agent or her representatives are unable effectively to enforce a claim to some state of affairs, I argue that she does not have a right to it. I stress, however, that if we approve of the claim she is trying to defend we may say that she ought to have a right to it, that is, that she ought to have an effectively enforceable claim. For example, a prisoner who is being beaten up does not have a right not to be tortured, though we are very likely to agree that she ought to have a right-that she should have effective protection from her torturers. Following Meckled-Garcia, I shall call this the Enforcement View. What advantages does the Enforcement View have? As Meckled-Garcia allows, one of its benefits is that it exposes what Onora O'Neill has called the 'empty rhetoric' of some rights talk. Rights are not secured, on this view, by merely acknowledging that agents possess morally legitimate claims of various sorts; we also have to ensure that these claims can be made good, so that possession of a right makes a practical difference to an agent's life. In this way, we avoid the irony of announcing that a group of famine victims has a right to food, or that a group of women has a right to abortion, in circumstances where neither group has a significant chance of getting what they have are said to have a right to. There are also at least three further benefits of this view, which Meckled-Garcia does not mention. First, as Raymond Geuss has pointed out, appeals to moral rights tend to obscure the difference between claims and moral judgments. Someone who says (in a jurisdiction where there is no provision for it) that gays have a right to same-sex marriage is voicing their belief that it ought to be possible to enforce this claim effectively, and is thus
Read full abstract