Abstract

Previous articleNext article No AccessSome Thoughts About RetributivismDavid DolinkoDavid Dolinko Search for more articles by this author PDFPDF PLUS Add to favoritesDownload CitationTrack CitationsPermissionsReprints Share onFacebookTwitterLinkedInRedditEmail SectionsMoreDetailsFiguresReferencesCited by Ethics Volume 101, Number 3Apr., 1991 Article DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1086/293316 Views: 59Total views on this site Citations: 48Citations are reported from Crossref Copyright 1991 The University of ChicagoPDF download Crossref reports the following articles citing this article:Zachary Hoskins Public Reason and the Justification of Punishment, Criminal Justice Ethics 2 (Aug 2022): 1–21.https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2022.2102838David Chelsom Vogt The Natural Meaning of Crime and Punishment: Denying and Affirming Freedom, Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (Nov 2021).https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-021-09624-2Victor Tadros Two grounds of liability, Philosophical Studies 178, no.1111 (Feb 2021): 3503–3522.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01611-6Michał Peno, Olgierd Bogucki Principles of Criminal Liability from the Semiotic Point of View, International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue internationale de Sémiotique juridique 34, no.22 (Mar 2020): 561–578.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-020-09691-zMichał Peno The Character of the Principles of Criminal Law and Criminal Responsibility: Between the Philosophy of Law and Semiotic, Liverpool Law Review 40, no.22 (Aug 2019): 79–93.https://doi.org/10.1007/s10991-019-09226-yHadar Dancig-Rosenberg, Netanel Dagan Retributarianism: A New Individualization of Punishment, Criminal Law and Philosophy 13, no.11 (Apr 2018): 129–147.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-018-9460-2David Alm , Criminal Law and Philosophy 13, no.11 ( 2019): 63.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-018-9459-8Peter Chau Bennett’s Expressive Justification of Punishment, Criminal Law and Philosophy 11, no.44 (May 2016): 661–679.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-016-9394-5Göran Duus-Otterström Fairness-Based Retributivism Reconsidered, Criminal Law and Philosophy 11, no.33 (Sep 2015): 481–498.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-015-9382-1R. A. Duff Legal Moralism, (Jun 2017): 1–9.https://doi.org/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee837Dana Kay Nelkin, Samuel C. Rickless The Relevance of Intention to Criminal Wrongdoing, Criminal Law and Philosophy 10, no.44 (Oct 2014): 745–762.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9343-0Alfred Allan Ethics in Psychology and Law: An International Perspective, Ethics & Behavior 25, no.66 (Feb 2015): 443–457.https://doi.org/10.1080/10508422.2014.952006 Rethinking the Freedom Question: 1978–1994, (Oct 2014): 344–424.https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139033602.012John Deigh Punishment and Proportionality, Criminal Justice Ethics 33, no.33 (Dec 2014): 185–199.https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2014.988429Frej Klem Thomsen There but for the Grace of My Orbitofrontal Cortex …, Criminal Justice Ethics 33, no.33 (Dec 2014): 220–235.https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2014.988520Liat Levanon Personhood, Equality, and a Possible Justification for Criminal Punishment, Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 27, no.22 (Jul 2015): 439–472.https://doi.org/10.1017/S0841820900006421Michael Da Silva Public Reason and the Need to Identify State-Relevant Desert, Criminal Justice Ethics 33, no.22 (Aug 2014): 129–154.https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2014.943977Nathan Hanna Retributivism revisited, Philosophical Studies 167, no.22 (Feb 2013): 473–484.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0103-0R. A. Duff Towards a Modest Legal Moralism, Criminal Law and Philosophy 8, no.11 (Oct 2012): 217–235.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-012-9191-8Peter Königs The Expressivist Account of Punishment, Retribution, and the Emotions, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16, no.55 (Jan 2013): 1029–1047.https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-013-9402-yZac Cogley Basic desert of reactive emotions, Philosophical Explorations 16, no.22 (Jun 2013): 165–177.https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2013.787441Geoffrey Cupit Desert, (Feb 2013).https://doi.org/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee720Derek S. Jeffreys Sending a Message: The Expressive View of Punishment, (Jan 2013): 83–101.https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137311788_5Robert F. Schopp Retribution and Revenge in the Context of Capital Punishment, SSRN Electronic Journal (Jan 2013).https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2239776 OhSeHyuk Philosophical Foundations of Punishment - focusing on New Trends of Punishment Theories in the USA and UK -, CHUNG_ANG LAW REVIEW 14, no.33 (Sep 2012): 7–40.https://doi.org/10.21759/caulaw.2012.14.3.7Whitley R. P. Kaufman Can Retributive Punishment Be Justified?, (Aug 2012): 47–72.https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4845-3_3Whitley R. P. Kaufman The Mixed Theory of Punishment, (Aug 2012): 73–92.https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4845-3_4Peter Chau Poverty, Distributive Justice, and Punishment, Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 25, no.11 (Jul 2015): 39–52.https://doi.org/10.1017/S0841820900005324Jim Staihar, Stephen Macedo Defending a Role for Mercy in a Criminal Justice System, (Oct 2011): 138–194.https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139030656.006Zachary Hoskins Fair Play, Political Obligation, and Punishment, Criminal Law and Philosophy 5, no.11 (Sep 2010): 53–71.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-010-9103-8Matthew H. Kramer Retributivism in the Spirit of Finnis, SSRN Electronic Journal (Jan 2011).https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1934746Alex Tuckness Retribution and Restitution in Locke’s Theory of Punishment, The Journal of Politics 72, no.33 (Jul 2015): 720–732.https://doi.org/10.1017/S0022381610000125Raffaele Rodogno GUILT, ANGER, AND RETRIBUTION, Legal Theory 16, no.11 (Jun 2010): 59–76.https://doi.org/10.1017/S1352325210000066Matt K. Stichter Rescuing Fair-Play as a Justification for Punishment, Res Publica 16, no.11 (Mar 2010): 73–81.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9119-xRichard L. Lippke Retributive Parsimony, Res Publica 15, no.44 (Sep 2009): 377–395.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-009-9101-7Michael Davis Punishment Theory’s Golden Half Century: A Survey of Developments from (about) 1957 to 2007, The Journal of Ethics 13, no.11 (Sep 2008): 73–100.https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-008-9040-0Nathan Hanna Say What? A Critique of Expressive Retributivism, Law and Philosophy 27, no.22 (Jul 2007): 123–150.https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-007-9014-6 by Mitchell N. Berman Punishment and Justification Berman, Ethics 118, no.22 (Jul 2015): 258–290.https://doi.org/10.1086/527424David Dolinko Reflections on the grammar of criminal law, Criminal Justice Ethics 27, no.11 (Jan 2008): 83–90.https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2008.9992231Pablo S. Torre Sympathy for the Devil? Child Homicide, Victim Characteristics, and the Sentencing Preferences of the American Conscience, SSRN Electronic Journal (Jan 2007).https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1310916Jeffrie G. Murphy Legal moralism and retribution revisited, Criminal Law and Philosophy 1, no.11 (Nov 2006): 5–20.https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-006-9000-3 by John Martin Fischer Punishment and Desert: A Reply to Dolinko Fischer, Ethics 117, no.11 (Jul 2015): 109–118.https://doi.org/10.1086/508038Bertrand Guillarme Bibliographie, (May 2003): 175–184.https://doi.org/10.3917/puf.guill.2003.01.0175 R. A. Duff Penal Communications: Recent Work in the Philosophy of Punishment, Crime and Justice 20 (Oct 2015): 1–97.https://doi.org/10.1086/449241David Dolinko Mismeasuring “unfair advantage”: A response to Michael Davis, Law and Philosophy 13, no.44 (Nov 1994): 493–524.https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02350481Michael Davis Criminal desert and unfair advantage: What's the connection?, Law and Philosophy 12, no.22 (May 1993): 133–156.https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02346476Michael S. Moore Justifying Retributivism, Israel Law Review 27, no.1-21-2 (Jul 2014): 15–49.https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021223700016836Dudley Knowles Unjustified Retribution, Israel Law Review 27, no.1-21-2 (Jul 2014): 50–58.https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021223700016848

Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call