Abstract

Representation is often taken as a kind of picturing-at least insofar as to picture something is to stand proxy for that thing, and to stand proxy on the basis of some sort of shared resemblance. Given the diversity of fields in which a notion of has gained a foothold, the sort of resemblance assumed may vary depending on the function of the proxy: resemblance might be perceptual, or structural, or in respect of interest, or with respect to informativeness. Even so, resemblance remains a vague notion, and picturing scarcely less so. This compound vagueness may be part of the charm of the notion of representation, and part of what makes it useful for fields ranging from political theory to the philosophy of art to cognitive science. But the vagueness of such a version of does not prevent it being suspect, nor should it prevent us from developing alternatives. Of course, there may well be contemporary notions of that (when properly understood) do not involve a picture-theory or any close relative thereof. But my object here is not so much to identify any central component of contemporary uses of as it is to diagnose a certain diagnosis of modernity-that is, a diagnosis of modernity, or at least of modern philosophy, that sees it as caught under the spell of a picture-theory of representation, and that thereby sees us as in need of disenchantment.1 On this view, modernity is born in the coming-to-dominance of such a picture-theory in the early modern works of Descartes, the Port-Royal logicians, and Leibniz, to name just a few of the favored candidates within philosophy. Its dominance might be explained by the acceptance by many an early modern philosopher, whether of a rationalist or an empiricist bent, of a split between the inner and the outer, such that the outer, public world is forced to reenact itself upon the stage of the private theater of the mind. I intend all due respect to theatrical notions of representation, but explanation of the dominance of some version of representation needs to take account of the early modern interest in the public realm of signs and symbols (written, drawn, or spoken) as much as of the importance of seemingly private ideas. So on the one hand, it may well be true that some notion of was an implicit underpinning of much that is characteristic of seventeenth-century thought. On the other hand, it is doubtful that the earliest of early modern notions of is appropriately described as a picture-theory. Indeed, I think that at least some early modern conceptions of are completely alien both to what we might think of today as and to what is often diagnosed as the origins of that thought. And that is just the reason why those early modern conceptions deserve our attention. For if we truly do find ourselves in the grip of suspect notions of representation, and if they supposedly are part of the philosophical patrimony of modernity, then one way to free ourselves might be to practice a kind of historical deconstruction of that inheritance-one that finds resources in the tradition itself with which to challenge the problematic picture-theory. It is with the aim of challenging the picturetheory of that I propose to examine a concrete example of picturing: namely, the painting Las Meninas with respect to what and how it represents. I make this proposal because the picture-theory cuts both ways: not only is often conceived as a sort of picturing,2 but pictures are taken to offer par-

Full Text
Paper version not known

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call

Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.