Abstract
In the early modern period necessity was tied to each of a clutch of interlocking notions: causation, laws of nature, essence, demonstration, logical inference, mathematical proof, etc. So, for example, some argued that if existence is of the essence of God, then God exists necessarily. Again, some argued that if the laws of motion are not known a priori but are discovered by experience, then they are not necessary. There was, however, no attempt to develop a typology of necessities, such as our contemporary distinctions among logical necessity, epistemic necessity, metaphysical necessity and nomic necessity. Indeed, a central concern of current-day interpreters of early modern texts is to disentangle claims about necessity in one domain, say, causation, from those in another, say, logic. Nor was the problem of necessity a desideratum for early modern philosophers to solve. There is a sense then in which it is slightly anachronistic even to speak of the problem of necessity in early modern philosophy. Nevertheless, the modal notion of necessity features prominently in early modern philosophy and it is important that we as modern-day interpreters of early modern texts find ways to understand and explain how it was understood. To that end, it will be helpful to find a general way of framing the problem of necessity in early modern philosophy. What I offer here is a two-stage analysis that aims to capture the broad contours of a cluster of problems that we would now call problems of necessity. As such, it provides a reference point against which different philosophers’ accounts of modal notions can be compared and assessed. The chapter has two sections. Section 1 presents a general heuristic for studying the problem of necessity in the early modern period, including a crucial development in the early modern view of necessary facts about the world. Section 2 applies that heuristic, by way of example, to the philosophy of John Locke. The General Problem of Necessity in Early Modern Philosophy Most early modern philosophers admit that some propositions are true irrespective of the way the world is and would be true even if there were no world.
Talk to us
Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have
Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.