Reviewed by: The Reformation of Philosophy ed. by Marius Timmann Mjaaland Mark Mattes The Reformation of Philosophy. Edited by Marius Timmann Mjaaland. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2020. viii + 279 pp. These eighteen essays present the results of the Sixth Nordic Conference for Philosophy of Religion held in Oslo in 2017. Their goal is to assess the impact of the Reformation on philosophy. Questions raised include: how did the Reformation re-situate philosophy? Was the Reformation in some sense a philosophical event? Strangely, the majority of thinkers tend to leapfrog from Luther, if he is examined at all, to German Idealism (Kant, Hegel, Schelling), Existentialism (Kierkegaard or Nietzsche), various schools of twentieth-century [End Page 362] phenomenology (Husserl and Heidegger), and postmodern thinkers (Derrida, Agamben, Badiou, and others). The theme is subdivided into four subthemes: (1) Re-Formation of Philosophy in Christianity and Islam, (2) Philosophy in the Wake of the Reformation, (3) Reformation, Phenomenology and Metaphysics, and (4) Critique, Protest and Reform. Many of the essays are fairly abstract and assume a working knowledge of current trends in philosophy. That said, those aware of the divergent schools in philosophy will find value in this book for assessing medium theory, communication theory, aesthetics, metaphysics, and hermeneutics in light of Luther in whom are “traces” of modern concepts. Editor Mjaaland sees many of the “deep structures” of modern philosophy as pre-figured in Luther. Some highlights include the following. Philipp Stoellger interprets Luther’s legacy for philosophy in light of medium theory. In this light, the Reformation is a “re-formatting” of religion and faith through the medium of the justifying word as well as other media by which God is self-revealing (43). Safet Bektovic, a Muslim scholar, follows the thinking of medieval Muslim mystic Ibn Arabi, who, similar to Luther’s notion of a “hidden God” (masks of God or larva dei), claims that Allah uses “signs” that reveal aspects of his presence while veiling his essence. Mjaaland shows how the destructive aspect of the theology of the cross, its crucifying of spiritual pride, impacted Heidegger and Kant who both use a notion of destruction to overthrow metaphysics. Ultimately, for Kant, however, the notion of God is problematic because it can neither be presupposed in experience nor proved, given that it is beyond sense experience. Stian Grøgaard appropriates the thinking of F. W. J. Schelling as a counter both to Kierkegaard’s skepticism of metaphysics and Hegel’s “speculative philosophy of Spirit” with an “a priori empiricism” which allows the logic of experience to permeate pure thought. Like Luther, the critique of philosophy is itself philosophical. Jayne Svennungsson also appeals to Schelling as a voice affirming Jewish experience in the face of German Idealism’s anti-Semitism. She notes that Jewish philosopher Franz Rosenzweig developed this further with a messianic vision that (ironically) challenges the nationalist [End Page 363] idea of one people as superior to all others, and makes this vision the vocation of the Jews. Jan-Olav Henriksen describes Nietzsche’s appreciation for Luther’s translation of the German Bible but otherwise develops Nietzsche’s wholesale rejection of Luther’s view of grace. Countering Protestant ambivalence towards aesthetics, Dorthe Jørgensen seeks an aesthetic which presents, and does not just represent, metaphysical truths. She appeals to Alexander Gottlieb Baumgartner and Kant to help in this quest and sees them as offering such an aesthetic based on dialogue with God. With respect to the traditional Lutheran doctrine of election, Atle Søvik defends the Book of Concord: “saying that people are sinners who should convert and presenting the grace of the gospel can be understood as a way that God creates faith . . . Thus blaming people for not having faith and God creating faith are two sides of the same event. They are not two contradictory events, but the same event” (238). This is a book by academics for academics. Perhaps an essay devoted to Luther as Nominalist would ground the material more in the Reformation legacy and serve as a frame of reference for the other essays. This book should be consulted only if one is invested in a specific theme or figure discussed in one of the...