It is time to rescue from dismal shadow of Darwinism. According to this now widely-discredited doctrine, human society is governed by the survival of fittest. Competition reigns unchecked. Individualism erodes any effort to cooperate. Ethics and morality become irrelevant. Some contend that social competition is very engine of human progress, and hence any effort to regulate it cannot be justified. Others accept competition as inevitable, even though they don't like it or do not endorse it ideologically. They seem persuaded that we cannot escape its reality. Natural selection, many reason, is ... well, natural. Natural, hence inviolable: What recourse could humans possibly have against laws of nature? Thus even people from divergent backgrounds seem to agree that this view of society unavoidably follows from evolution. Creationists, not surprisingly, parade it as reason to reject outright (Bergman 2006). By contrast, as resolute an evolutionist as Thomas Henry Huxley, bulldog, invoked similar implications even while he urged his audience to transcend them morally (1894/1989). Yet core assumptions of so called Social Darwinism are unwarranted. Why does it continue to haunt us? The time has come to dislodge this entrenched belief, this sacred bovine: that nature somehow dictates a fundamentally individualistic and competitive society. Unraveling flawed argument behind also yields a more general-and much more important-lesson about nature of science. Here, historical argument seemed to enlist science to portray certain cultural perspectives as facts of nature. Naturalizing cultural ideas in this way is all too easy. Cultural contexts seem to remain invisible to those within culture itself, sometimes scientists, too. The case of Darwinism--not at all--illustrates vividly how appeals to science can go awry. We might thus learn how to notice, and to remedy or guard against such errors in other cases. Social Darwinism Without Darwin Ironically, basic doctrine now labeled did not originate with Darwin himself. Darwin was no Darwinist. Quite contrary: Darwin opened way for understanding how a moral society can evolve (last month's Sacred Bovines). Indeed, by Darwin's era, notion of unregulated selfishness as a condition that threatened social order was centuries-old. In mid-1600s, for example, Thomas Hobbes described primitive state of nature as bellum omnium contra omnes: a of each against all. For him, supreme individualism (if left unchecked) would eclipse sociality. Even genuine benevolence seemed impossible. In Hobbes's cynical spin, generosity was really disguised self-interest: For no man giveth but with intention of good to himself, because gift is voluntary; and of all voluntary acts object is to every man his own good. (1651/1962, p. 118) Hobbes's proposed solution was to imagine a social contract. If everyone agreed mutually to limit self-serving behavior, all would benefit. If. As in a legal system, who enforced contract? One would need a moral authority outside or above system (for Hobbes, it was King). The dilemma of cheaters and warrant for authority--the lack of moral grounding--was same that critics of evolution now fault in Darwinism. And it resulted from same basic assumptions: individualism and war of nature--all posited without (and well before) Darwin. Darwinist perspectives were also expressed by Thomas Malthus in his 1798 Essay on Principle of Population and in its many subsequent editions. For Malthus, population would forever increase ahead of ability to feed it. The natural inequality of population and production, he claimed, confuted romantic ideals (then prevalent) of social improvement: Necessity, that imperious all pervading law of nature, restrains them [the seeds of life] within prescribed bounds. …
Read full abstract