reviews 535 ofimagining thatideas and solutions can be imposedfromabove,and who allegedly finditdifficult eventodaytograspthat'somedilemmas thatappear philosophical cannotbe answered philosophically' (p. 201). Intellectuals are not the onlygroupto be subjectedto thisbroad-brush approach;thestudy is regularly punctuated bygeneralized references to the perceptions and reactions of'readers'and 'critics' as well.We are toldthat critics imaginedthattherewas 'no artistry, no meaningin Tolstoybeyond thatofdirectexperience oflife,and so he had nothing to teachus' (p 11); thattheyseem 'to have sharedAnna's perspective and romantic viewsso thoroughly thattheycannotimaginethe authorwould differ' (p. 87); that readers, too,'misreadthenovelas a bookcelebrating highdramaand grand romance'(p. 37);that,in Emma, readers'come to realizethedeficiencies of theheroine's waysofperception', whereas, inAnna Karenina, 'toomanydo not' (p. 87). There is hardlya sentencein thisbook thatdoes not have something arresting orchallenging tosay.Morsondismisses a number ofreceived 'myths', including theviewthatthereis an allegorical connection betweenthedeath ofVronskii's horseFrou-Frou and Anna'ssuicide,and thestandard explanationsof the novel'sepigraph, forwhichhe advanceshis own 'unexpected' interpretation. Karenin'shumanqualitiesare emphasized, although Morson showshimas turning intoa 'moralmonster' after hisconversion. The close readingofKareninand hisrelationship withAnnais one ofthebook'smany highlights, together withtheanalysis ofLevinand thequestionofagricultural reform in chapterfour. Thisstudy isTolstoyan, intoneas wellas content, and thefactthatitends withover ten pages of 'one hundredsixtythreeTolstoyanconclusions'is appropriate. Littleweightis givento thepossibility thattheremightbe a middlewaybetweenextreme positions. I emerged from thisbookmuchas I often do after readingTolstoihimself, havingexperienced thewholegamut ofreactions from 'Yes, thatis absolutely right! How can I havenotseenthat before?'to 'No, that'sreallyunfair! I mustgo and checkthisformyself. Morson'sintention in writing thisstudy was 'to open debate,notto closeit' (p. 5); he has succeededbrilliantly. Exeter Roger Cogkrell de la Durantaye,Leland. Style Is Matter: TheMoralArtof Vladimir Nabokov. CornellUniversity Press,Ithaca,NY and London,2007.viii+ 211pp. Illustrations. Notes.Bibliography. Index.$39.95:£20.50. Leland de la Durantaye's bookfocuses on theproblemofhowone should read Lolita, in particular, whatattitude one shouldtaketo itsprotagonistnarrator . Using Eichmann'srejectionof this'immoral'book as his springboard , the authornegotiates betweenthe unsatisfactory 'art-for-art's-sake' perspective and the equallyunacceptableview of VladimirNabokov as a warmcosymoralist. The answerthathe offers pertains toNabokov'spoetics, 536 seer, 87, 3, July 2009 especiallyhis view of styleas a 'moral stancereflected in formalchoice' (p. 191).The stanceis 'moral'notbecauseitconveys a messagebutbecause, according to thiscritical study, thenovelengagesin moralissues.Whatthe study likewise suggests is thatartistic excellence, complete withthebalanced and modulatedtreatment ofone's material, createsconditions foran ethical response. The ethicsoftheworkis itsinherent quality, notreducible towhat Nabokovcalledhaving'a moralin tow'. The book does not engagein actual textanalysisthatwould show,on concrete instances, whatis so really good aboutNabokov'sstyle, yetitgoesa longwaytowards preparing a conceptual basisforsuchan analysis. The line ofthought windsthrough a seriesofshort sections, each devotedtoa specific issueinNabokov'sownpoeticsorincritical literature abouthim.The reader is in suspense,waitingforthe engagements withtheseissuesto converge. The expectation is, indeed,ultimately fulfilled; in themeantimea bonusis offered tous at manyturns ofthepath,either intheshapeofinformation on Nabokov'sEuropeancontexts or hisunpublished correspondence, or in the shape ofseparateinsights. One ofsuchexcellent observations, whichcould map avenuesoffurther research, isthatportions oí Lolita shift 'thetraditional poles of ethicalresponse:the categorical and the conditional? (p. 14).In other words,in LolitaNabokov stagesa tensionbetweenthe prima-facie ethics, according towhichcertain things areplainly nottobe done,and theall-thingsconsidered morality, whose evaluativeagenda takesintoaccountthe sundry extenuating circumstances and individualconditions. HumbertHumbert's claimon thereader'sunderstanding is rootedin thelatter approach,though deep downevenhe is notunresponsive to theclaimsoftheformer. A numberofpointsin de la Durantaye'sbook can elicitprotest - for instanceagainstwhatlookslikethe author'sall too readyconcurrence in Nabokov'srejectionofJoyce'sFinnegans Wake(he willprobablychangehis mindone day).Moreimportantly, itisunfortunate thatde la Durantaye joins thecommentators who ascribe'cruelty' to Nabokov- not to some of his characters butto thenovelist himself, sincean arrayofhistechniques keeps pointingto the inadequaciesof our reading,attentiveness and erudition. Thoughde la Durantaye ultimately suggests thatthenovelist may'havebeen cruelto be kind'(p. 179),theissueof cruelty is hererathermisguided. In Contingency, Irony, andSolidarity RichardRortydiscusses Nabokovas a liberal, one who (borrowing JudithShklar'sterms)thinks thatcruelty is theworst thingwe do. Admittedly, Rortywas not rightin everything he said about Nabokov,but his comments on thetreatment ofcruelty and callousness in Lolita areofmajorimportance. Itmust, indeed,be notedthatNabokovdenies his readersthe complacency of aesthetic bliss,but such pricking of our selfsatisfaction , our senseofunavoidableunder-reading alternates withthejoy ofdiscoveries that,as mostofNabokovcritics can testify, giveeach ofus an illusion ofbeingsingled out,granted a glimpse ofwhatmaybe hiddenfrom others. I also disagree withde la Durantaye's accounting forNabokov'sobjections to Marx,Freudand Darwinbythegenerality oftheir theories. Adherents of thesetheories tendto formclosed systems withinwhicheverything...
Read full abstract