Abstract

When contemporary scholars read and interpret historical architectural treatises, one dimension that is frequently lost from the original works is their moral or ethical values. For example, when John Ruskin argues that there are right and wrong geometric shapes in architecture, he may be talking about the difference between mechanical Euclidean curves and freehand quasi-logarithmic ones, but he is, more importantly, also talking about lines that are not simply geometrically but morally correct as well. Similarly, the texts of Vitruvius and Alberti contain rules for the ideal construction of architectural form, but this rightness is first and foremost a moral or ethical quality that is symbolically embodied in a geometric construction. However, while the geometric construction of historic and modern architecture remains the subject of considerable research today, the ethical dimensions in the same architectural techniques tend to be forgotten or are often considered irrelevant to the work. One reason for this shift away from a consideration of the moral dimension in design is, as Levine, Miller and Taylor [2004] observe, that the concept of an ethics of architecture has become increasingly problematic over the last few centuries. This is because throughout the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries philosophers persuasively argued that only human actions can have ethical connotations. Inanimate and non-sentient objects such as architecture are assumed to be without innate ethical capacity because they do not necessarily shape human responses, actions or behaviours. While in recent years the anthropocentric focus of ethics has been successfully challenged and broadened to include consideration of animals, plants and ecosystems, manufactured or synthetic objects have remained largely excluded from the ethical domain.

Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call