Abstract

I. Introduction Jacques Maritain once quipped that can be more remote from the facts than the belief that 'personalism' is one school or doctrine, as some philosophies have nothing more in common than the term 'person.' (1) Nevertheless, there are at least several distinguishing features of any genuinely philosophy: a belief in the unbridgeable divide between persons and nonpersons, and in the inalienable dignity of the former; an emphasis on a person's incommunicability or uniqueness; a defense of the personalist norm, which states that persons ought to be affirmed for their own sake (or ought never to be treated merely as means to an end); and, finally, the rejection of any political system that subordinates a to the social whole or, conversely, that marginalizes a person's obligations toward the common good. (2) If these are accurate standards for identifying a system or thinker, then Thomas Aquinas appears to be a paradigmatic personalist, at least at first glance. He certainly thinks that the difference between persons and nonpersons is a difference in kind, not degree. (3) He also defends the inherent dignity of persons by arguing that the term person refers to is most perfect in all of nature. (4) Further, he thinks that a is incommunicable or radically unique because she is individuated in part through her freely performed actions. (5) With respect to how we ought to treat persons, he says that a ought to be loved with the love of friendship, which involves willing the good of a for that person's own sake. (6) And, finally, Aquinas states that a human person, as a member of the species Homo sapiens, must at times subordinate her good for the sake of the common good; however, this does not make her a mere part within a whole, because she is willed by God for her own sake (or as an end in herself). (7) True, Aquinas does not give us a systematic or complete personalism, but (according to the above criteria) he certainly seems to be a thinker. Karol Wojtyia goes so far as to argue that a broadly Thomistic anthropology and ethics are necessary for grounding an adequate personalism. And he makes this argument despite criticizing Aquinas for failing to explore personal subjectivity and lived experience. In sum, Wojtyia focuses on what he takes to be missing in Aquinas's account of the person, but he affirms and defends its underlying metaphysical principles. (8) Josef Seifert, however, offers a different kind of critique in his Personalism and Personalisms, one that questions the suitability of Aquinas's principles for grounding an adequate personalism. His central argument is that Aquinas's account of the good is incompatible with the respect owed to persons--because Aquinas thinks that something is good only in relation to an appetite, a can be good for another, but not in himself. In what follows, I argue that Seifert's critique fails because he misreads Aquinas's metaethical claims. In particular, he fails to appreciate Aquinas's understanding of the ecstatic (or other-directed) nature of being and goodness. If my interpretation of Aquinas is correct, then his metaphysical principles can ground the proper respect owed to persons. They are, in fact, ideal for doing so. I conclude by suggesting that Seifert's own account of the good needlessly creates a divide between a and his desires, and thereby creates problems for his account of moral motivation. II. Seifert on Aquinas as a Personalist Thinker Seifert does acknowledge that personalism owes a genuine debt to Aquinas: St. Thomas is in a great many respects not only a thinker, but even a true model of a metaphysician. (9) As I noted earlier, however, he thinks that Aquinas's understanding of goodness precludes the possibility of affirming a for her own sake, which is the only appropriate response to the dignity of personhood. …

Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call