Abstract

Beliefs have what I will call ‘propositional content’. A belief is always a belief that so-and-so: a belief that grass is green, or a belief that snow is white, or whatever. Other things have propositional content too, such as sentences, judgments and assertions. The Standard View amongst philosophers is that what it is to have a propositional content is to stand in an appropriate relation to a proposition. Moreover, on this view, propositions are objects, i.e. the kind of thing you can refer to with singular terms. For example, on the Standard View, we should parse the sentence ‘Simon believes that Sharon is funny’ as: [Simon] believes [that Sharon is funny]; ‘Simon’ is a term referring to a thinking subject, ‘that Sharon is funny’ is a term referring to a proposition, and ‘x believes y’ is a dyadic predicate expressing the believing relation. In this paper, I argue against the Standard View. This is how I think we should parse ‘Simon believes that Sharon is funny’: [Simon] believes that [Sharon is funny]; here we have a singular term, ‘Simon’, a sentence ‘Sharon is funny’, and a ‘prenective’ joining them together, ‘x believes that p’. On this Prenective View, we do not get at the propositional content of someone’s belief by referring to a reified proposition with a singular term; we simply use the sentence ‘Sharon is funny’ to express that content for ourselves. I argue for the Prenective View in large part by showing that an initially attractive version of the Standard View is actually vulnerable to the same objection that Wittgenstein used against Russell’s multiple-relation theory of judgment.

Highlights

  • Beliefs have what I will call propositional content

  • As a rough gloss, we can say that something has a propositional content just in case it has a content that can be expressed by a sentence

  • There surely is a more neutral notion of propositional content, platitudinously related to the notion of truth-aptitude, which is correctly applied to propositions on the Standard View: that view plainly requires that propositions be truth-apt, and nothing can be true or false unless it in some sense says something

Read more

Summary

Introduction

Beliefs have what I will call propositional content. A belief is always a belief that soand-so: a belief that grass is green, or a belief that snow is white, or whatever. The Standard View goes further by reifying propositions: it treats propositions as objects that can be referred to with singular terms. On the Prenective View, there is no term referring to a proposition in ‘Simon believes that Sharon is funny’. This sentence does not, express a relation between Simon and a reified proposition. Instead of getting at the content of Simon’s belief by referring to a proposition, we use the sentence ‘Sharon is funny’ to express that content for ourselves. 3, I will present a simple, and I think fatal, objection to a completely general version of that view: propositions have propositional contents, but it would be incoherent to apply the Standard View to propositions themselves.

Why start from the Standard View?
The contents of propositions
A truth-conditional approach
The constituents of propositions
Wittgenstein’s objection
Russell’s multiple-relation theory of judgment
The problem of nonsensical judgments
The expressive impossibility of nonsensical judgments
Two types of type-restriction
The collapse of Russell’s multiple-relation theory
Back to the constituents of propositions
Conclusion: truth on the Prenective View
Full Text
Paper version not known

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call

Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.