Abstract
It is not without irony that philosophers in the twentieth century have developed an argument for the existence of God from religious experience. Religious experience as such emerged as a philosophical concern in the nineteenth century, when it became apparent that theology had been dealt a severe blow by the skeptical philosophers of the Enlightenment, especially Hume and Kant. In an attempt to save religion Schleiermacher, in particular, distinguished it from philosophical and theological reflection and declared it to be essentially a feeling, a unique subjective experience. Thus, religion was withdrawn from a sphere in which it is bound always to appear problematic and relocated closer to its immediate sources in life, where it is quite natural. But this move, although appreciated by Otto, Eliade, and others of the phenomenological school of religious studies, has been somewhat frustrated by the tendency of modern philosophers to ask, does religious experience somehow prove the existence of God?1 In the present essay I shall show how the typical philosophical preoccupation with demonstrable knowledge, when it comes to religious matters - in this case, the matter of finding a proof for the existence of God based on religious experience - sets up a no-win situation for religion, a situation in which it can only appear false. For it takes religion to be something it is not - viz., as having cognitive content in a scientific sense - thereby making demands on it that it cannot possibly live up to. Indeed, I shall suggest that religious utterances do have cognitive content; nevertheless, they have a quite different kind than scientific sentences, due to the fact that they occur in a context of faith, a fundamentally different, but nevertheless bona fide, epistemological situation than science (faith may be opposed to science, but it is not opposed to knowledge). The basic error of the philosophical effort to evaluate religious claims - that is, to determine whether they are valid or not; there are, of course other senses in which religious experience can be evaluated - is that it removes them from their context of faith. My final position - a statement of which can only appear somewhat cryptic at this stage - is that a philosophical study of religious experience should be less concerned with whether we should accept the claims made on the basis of religious experience than why, in the context of faith, we often do.
Full Text
Topics from this Paper
Religious Experience
Scientific Sense
Cognitive Content
Context Of Faith
Final Position
+ Show 5 more
Create a personalized feed of these topics
Get StartedTalk to us
Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have
Similar Papers
Jul 1, 2009
Nova et vetera
Sep 1, 2022
Journal of Religion and Human Relations
Nov 16, 2022
Jan 1, 2005
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Jan 1, 1984
Journal of Philosophical Theological Research
May 22, 2014
The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review
Jan 1, 2017
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Jan 1, 1985
The Journal of Speculative Philosophy
Jan 1, 2019
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Jun 1, 1982
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Nov 14, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Oct 20, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Sep 22, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Sep 7, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Aug 17, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Aug 11, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Jul 10, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Jul 4, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Jun 23, 2023
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
Jun 20, 2023