Abstract
In their comparative analysis of Randomised Clinical Trials and observational studies, Papanikoloau et al. (2006) assert that “it may be unfair to invoke bias and confounding to discredit observational studies as a source of evidence on harms”. There are two kinds of answers to the question why this is so. One is based on metaphysical assumptions, such as the problem of causal sufficiency, modularity and other statistical assumptions. The other is epistemological and relates to foundational issues and how they determine the constraints we put on evidence. I will address here the latter dimension and present recent proposals to amend evidence hierarchies for the purpose of safety assessment of pharmaceuticals; I then relate these suggestions to a case study: the recent debate on the causal association between paracetamol and asthma. The upshot of this analysis is that different epistemologies impose different constraints on the methods we adopt to collect and evaluate evidence; thus they grant “lower level” evidence on distinct grounds and at different conditions. Appreciating this state of affairs illuminates the debate on the epistemic asymmetry concerning benefits and harms and sets the basis for a foundational, as opposed to heuristic, justification of safety assessment based on heterogeneous evidence.
Highlights
Evidence standards are supposed to provide “quick and dirty rules” for assessing the quality of evidence, as a function of the greatest possible reduction of confounding and bias
Different epistemologies grant different methodological actions and grant “lower level” evidence on distinct grounds and at different conditions, it is worthy and crucial to bear in mind the criteria underlying the evidence constraints one imposes on oneself
Appreciating this state of affairs illuminates the debate on the epistemic asymmetry concerning benefit and harm assessment and sets the basis for a foundational, as opposed to heuristic, justification of evidential support for pharmaceutical harm
Summary
Evidence standards are supposed to provide “quick and dirty rules” for assessing the quality of evidence, as a function of the greatest possible reduction of confounding and bias. After presenting his nine guidelines for detecting and assessing causal relationships he claims: “None of my nine viewpoints can bring indisputable evidence for or against the cause-and-effect hypothesis and none can be required as a sine qua non.
Talk to us
Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have
Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.