Abstract

Reviewed by: Personification and the Feminine in Roman Philosophy by Alex Dressler G. Reydams-Schils Alex Dressler. Personification and the Feminine in Roman Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016. xiii + 312 pp. Cloth, £80. This book is a bit of a wild ride, which makes it enjoyable and intellectually stimulating, in the eyes of this reviewer at least. But there may well be too much going on, with the impressive range of intellectual resources from which Alex Dressler draws. Many of his footnotes could be turned into graduate seminars. The core idea, as the author himself summarizes it (253), is as follows: "it was the aesthetic artifact of the feminine, in the form of the personifications of grammatically feminine abstractions, that the Roman philosopher persistently included in his attempt to understand who and what he was, and it was this that escaped his effort and his unflagging interest in discriminating male and female." This aesthetic dimension, Dressler argues, opens up the possibility of a "reparative" reading not only of ancient accounts, but also of our own current condition, and therefore of hope, feminist and other. Dressler's primary method is that of post-modern deconstruction, according to which any attempt at creating binaries is inherently unstable and ends up undermining itself. In his analysis of Roman philosophy he also brings to bear ancient theories of rhetoric and grammar, as well as literary theory, and other strands in the ancient tradition. His use of "ownness," for instance, allows him to group together philosophical notions such as the Stoic "appropriation" (oikeiôsis) and any number of literary and rhetorical devices that express subjectivity and personhood, and that are sometimes overlooked in current treatments of Roman philosophy. But here, instead of questioning the very binary construct of philosophy versus literature (or rhetoric) itself, the author adopts too much of an apologetic tone, and spends too much effort on a discourse of self-justification arguing against the current dominant mode of philosophy in Anglo-American circles. The distinction between philosophy and literature is an anachronism. If instead we define "philosophy" in terms the ancients themselves used, a much richer picture emerges, and the division between argument and metaphor is no longer tenable. The crucial question becomes not what metaphors do in the midst of a philosophical exposition, but what philosophical contribution is made by them qua metaphors. But perhaps the author needs metaphors to remain on the other side of philosophical discourse to allow for what he has called the "aesthetic feminine" to exert its (salutary) disruptive influence. In accounts of Roman philosophers such as Cicero, Lucretius, and Seneca, Dressler sees a subversive feminine at work—of traits usually attributed to women such as passivity, dependence, and embodiment—that undermines the attempts at construing masculinity and relegating women to the status of the excluded and socially inferior (the "subaltern"). This subversion can take place at different levels and through a range of processes. 1. The intellectual rigor of this work shines through especially in its conceptual apparatus (Ch. 2). Personhood, Dressler posits, always incorporates a third-person perspective; one is constituted as a person also insofar as one [End Page 568] is seen and shaped by others. In a process which Dressler calls dynamic personification (76ff.), when a Roman male subject constitutes himself as a person he may be erasing his original dependence on women and relegating the feminine to the level of personification, but these feminine personifications such as Natura end up being indispensable to the constitution of himself as a person. Thus, in such personifications the feminine reenters, and gender roles are reversed when, for instance, a male agent passively submits to the agency of personified Nature qua grammatically feminine. Through the process of dynamic personification the male self comes to realize its fundamental dependency on others. Dressler illustrates this core idea with an analysis of the widely discussed passages from Book Three of Cicero's On Ends on the role of nature in the Stoic process of "appropriation" (3.16ff. and 3.62–4; Ch. 3). But these passages immediately raise questions that could undermine Dressler's mode of reading. First, even when Nature is represented as an agent...

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call

Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.