Abstract

At first glance the conjunction of phenomenology and practice seems to be a contradiction in terms. Husserl’s phenomenology is informed by the exercise of the epoché, where we suspend every thesis that we have regarding the natural world. The result, Husserl declares, is that the epoché “utterly closes off for me every judgment about spatiotemporal existence.” Its focus is not on such existence, but on the evidence we have for it. Does this mean that phenomenology is forever shut off from the realm of praxis – that it cannot concern itself with the ethical and political issues that confront us? For Patočka, this conclusion fails to take account of the freedom presupposed by the epoché. Such freedom, he writes, is “grounded in our inherent freedom to step back, to dissociate ourselves from entities.” It is not the result of some act of consciousness. It is, rather, our ontological condition, it is “what characterizes humans as such.” If this is true, then the practice of the epoché actually opens up phenomenology to practical questions. If the epoché presupposes our freedom – the freedom that is at issue in such questions – then the epoché also presupposes the engagement – the being-in-the-world – of our praxis. It does not suspend this engagement, but rather discloses it – this, by showing that freedom is the ultimate residuum left by the epoché. The thesis of my paper is that this insight allows Patočka to transform Husserlian phenomenology. In his hands, phenomenology conjoins the epistemological with the practical by seeing them both in terms of the freedom definitive of us. By examining what Patočka calls “the motion of human existence,” I delineate the nature of this transformation.

Highlights

  • At first glance the conjunction of phenomenology and practice seems to be a contradiction in terms

  • Husserl’s phenomenology is informed by the exercise of the epoché, where we suspend every thesis that we have regarding the natural world

  • Its focus is not on such existence, but on the evidence we have for it. Does this mean that phenomenology is forever shut off from the realm of praxis – that it cannot concern itself with the ethical and political issues that confront us? For Patočka, this conclusion fails to take account of the freedom presupposed by the epoché

Read more

Summary

Practical Philosophy and the Freedom of the Epoché

In his description of practical wisdom or phronesis (φρόνησις) gives us the clearest definition of practical philosophy. When we perform the epoché, we suspend every thesis we have regarding the natural world This means that we “‘put it out of action,’ we ‘exclude it,’ we ‘bracket it.’”12 The result, Husserl declares, is that the epoché “completely closes off for me every judgment about spatiotemporal existence.”[13] Its focus is not on such existence, but on the evidence we have for it. Its endeavor is epistemological rather than practical Does this mean that phenomenology is forever shut off from the realm of praxis – that it cannot concern itself with the ethical and political issues that confront us? “the method of bracketing” must be “definitely restricted.”[14] It cannot apply to the consciousness engaging in the epoché If it did, all judgments concerning its contents would be suspended.[15] At this point, even the epistemological task of examining the evidence for our judgments would have to be abandoned. This engagement must, in other words, remain as a residuum of the epoché.[24]

Pragmatic Disclosure
The Ontological Difference and the Question of Appearing as Such
Care For Appearing
The Transformation of Phenomenology
Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call