Abstract
It is a truism that conceptual understanding of a hypothesis is required for its empirical investigation. However, the concept of recursion as articulated in the context of linguistic analysis has been perennially confused. Nowhere has this been more evident than in attempts to critique and extend Hauseretal's. (2002) articulation. These authors put forward the hypothesis that what is uniquely human and unique to the faculty of language—the faculty of language in the narrow sense (FLN)—is a recursive system that generates and maps syntactic objects to conceptual-intentional and sensory-motor systems. This thesis was based on the standard mathematical definition of recursion as understood by Gödel and Turing, and yet has commonly been interpreted in other ways, most notably and incorrectly as a thesis about the capacity for syntactic embedding. As we explain, the recursiveness of a function is defined independent of such output, whether infinite or finite, embedded or unembedded—existent or non-existent. And to the extent that embedding is a sufficient, though not necessary, diagnostic of recursion, it has not been established that the apparent restriction on embedding in some languages is of any theoretical import. Misunderstanding of these facts has generated research that is often irrelevant to the FLN thesis as well as to other theories of language competence that focus on its generative power of expression. This essay is an attempt to bring conceptual clarity to such discussions as well as to future empirical investigations by explaining three criterial properties of recursion: computability (i.e., rules in intension rather than lists in extension); definition by induction (i.e., rules strongly generative of structure); and mathematical induction (i.e., rules for the principled—and potentially unbounded—expansion of strongly generated structure). By these necessary and sufficient criteria, the grammars of all natural languages are recursive.
Highlights
THREE PROPERTIES OF RECURSION The theory of recursive functions was propounded in the foundations of mathematics
It is of fundamental importance to understand that the non-arbitrary set generated by a recursive function qua Turing machine need not be represented as an output; to recursively generate a set is not to produce it
The Post formalism represents explicitly the recursiveness of a generative grammar, with outputs recursed as inputs in the form of recursion applied by Gödel and represented in the stepwise computation of a Turing machine: i.e., definition by induction whereby a function f is defined for an argument x by a previously defined value (e.g., f (y), y < x) so as to strongly generate increasingly complex structures carried forward on the tape
Summary
THREE PROPERTIES OF RECURSION The theory of recursive functions was propounded in the foundations of mathematics. The Post formalism represents explicitly the recursiveness of a generative grammar, with outputs recursed (returned) as inputs in the form of recursion applied by Gödel and represented in the stepwise computation of a Turing machine: i.e., definition by induction (definition by recursion) whereby a function f is defined for an argument x by a previously defined value (e.g., f (y), y < x) so as to strongly generate increasingly complex structures carried forward on the tape.
Talk to us
Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have
Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.