Abstract

Proponents of the predicate view of names explain the reference of an occurrence of a name N by invoking the property of bearing N. They avoid the charge that this view involves a vicious circularity by claiming that bearing N is not itself to be understood in terms of the reference of actual or possible occurrences of N. I argue that this approach is fundamentally mistaken. The phenomenon of 'reference transfer' shows that an individual can come to bear a name in virtue of the referential practices of a group of speakers. I develop a picture of name-bearing which captures this fact by treating the extension of name as a function of the way that extension is represented in the presuppositions of groups of speakers. I show that though there is a form of circularity inherent in this approach, it is not vicious circularity.

Highlights

  • Proponents of the predicate view of names explain the reference of an occurrence of a name N by invoking the property of bearing N

  • The semantic component of the theory holds that proper names are predicates - that is, they express properties of individuals

  • PV holds that proper names express metalinguistic properties

Read more

Summary

Circularity

Anyone who has recently advocated for PV has felt the need to respond to an influential argument in [Kripke, 1980]. Note that the proposal Kripke is attacking here is not precisely PV He seems to have in mind a view which treats names as simple referential terms whose reference is fixed by a uniquely identifying descriptive condition (“the man that I call ‘Glunk’ ”). If we hold to Kripke’s thought that name-bearing facts are determined by name-reference facts we are faced with circularity. It is no more essential to the property of bearing a certain name that one be referred to by that name than it is essential to the property of having a certain social security number that one be referred to by that number [Bach, 2002, 83] Both writers are explicitly responding to the circularity worry. One can use the predicate Alfred to refer to someone who bears that name for example, by employing a definite description of the form thenull Alfred. The standard picture of name-bearing associated with PV cannot capture these cases precisely because they reveal a dimension in which facts about name-bearing depend on facts about reference

Name-bearing according to the Predicate View
Name-bearing and presupposition
Circularity redux
Groups of speakers
Summing up
Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call