Abstract

The paper studies Wald's minimax risk (M.R.) criterion and Lehmann's unbiasedness condition for a very general class of Type I problems (Section 2) which contains nearly all nonsequential multiple decision problems (m.d.p.'s) from parametric statistics (at least when no reasonable a priori knowledge is available--apart from knowledge restricting parameter space in, for example, one-sided problems or in trend situations--and provided that problems can be formulated by means of a loss function which is constant for various kinds of error.) Type I problems turn out to behave in a degenerate way. Generally M.R. procedure is not unique (Situation 1, see Theorem 3.1 and Sections 5, 11, 12); when a unique M.R. procedure exists, then this is trivial and useless (Situation 2, see Corollary 3.1 and Sections $6, \cdots, 10$). We try to remedy this by applying Lehmann's unbiasedness condition (Section 4). This has to be done cautiously for unbiasedness condition might be too restrictive: sometimes class $W$ of all unbiased procedures is so small (Corollary 4.1) that $W = \varnothing$ (Theorem 8.1(i)) or such that $W$ contains only poor and useless procedures (Theorem 8.1 (iii) and Section 12). Fortunately we can show for some problems in Situation 1 that $W \subset M$ where $M$ denotes class of all M. R. procedures (cf. Theorem 4.1; unbiasedness restriction seems to be very attractive when sufficient conditions of Lemma 4.2 are satisfied, see Theorem 5.1 where $W = M,$ Lemma 7.1 (ii) and Theorem 11.1; in Section 12 we also have $W \subset M$ but nevertheless unbiasedness restriction is not attractive). For problems in Situation 2 unique M.R. procedure $\delta^\ast$ is trivial and useless. Nevertheless we regard it as an advantage of unbiasedness restriction when $\delta^\ast \varepsilon W$ (Sections 6, $\cdots$, 10), whereas $\delta^\ast \not\in W$ is regarded as an indication that $W$ might be too small (Theorem 8.1 (iv), Remark 8.1 and Lemma 10.1). We always try to obtain procedure with the most attractive appropriate property. As shown by Lehmann ordinary two-decision testing problems (Section 5) and products of such problems (Section 11) do not present extensive difficulties because unbiasedness restriction is attractive (Theorems 5.1 and 11.1) and reduces our m.d.p.'s to problems in Neyman-Pearson formulation. Many three-decision two-sided problems are solved (Section 6) though we have to be content with criterions which are not very compelling. Similar results are obtained for some slippage problems (Sections 7, $\cdots$, 9) where optimum procedure turns out to be not of natural form considered in literature. For many m.d.p.'s of Type I (except for those in Sections 5, 6 and 11) actual construction of optimum procedure is forbidding and we have to content ourselves with results relating classes $W$ and $M$ (cf. Sections 7, $\cdots$, 10, 12; problems can be solved only in very simple special cases).

Full Text
Paper version not known

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call

Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.