Abstract

This Article identifies an anomalous discrepancy between law and epistemology and proposes a way to fix it. Our legal system relies on decisions of multimember tribunals, which include juries, state and federal appellate courts and supreme courts. Members of those tribunals often disagree with each other on matters of fact. When this happens, the system settles the disagreement by applying head-counting rules: the unanimity or supermajority requirement for jury verdicts and the majority rule for judges’ decisions. Under these rules, jurors can return an agreed-upon verdict even when their reasons for supporting that verdict are inconsistent with one another. Similarly, judges are authorized to deliver any decision so long as it is supported by a majority of the panel. Disagreements among judges and jurors are consequently ironed out instead of being accounted for as a factor that reduces the reliability of the contested decision. By adopting these rules, our legal system allows jurors to convict the defendant when six of them believe the incriminating account provided by one witness, while rejecting as incredible the testimony of another prosecution witness, and the remaining six jurors form a diametrically opposite view of the two witnesses’ credibility. Moreover, the system authorizes appellate courts to determine by a narrow 2-1 majority that a violation of the accused’s constitutional trial right was “harmless beyond a reasonable doubt.” Likewise, it accords the status of an unreservedly binding precedent to a 5-4 decision of the United States Supreme Court that determines the meaning of a statutory or constitutional provision. These rules are fundamentally incompatible with the epistemological principles of rational fact-finding. The epistemology of disagreement has recently given rise to a simple, yet powerful, analytical insight: when a person makes a factual finding based on all available information and then realizes that an equally informed and honest individual — an “epistemic peer” — arrived at a different conclusion, she ought to scale down her level of confidence in her own opinion. A peer’s disagreement is evidence writ large that a person cannot rationally ignore or discount. Rather, she must give it weight and revisit her original opinion. Under this epistemological mandate, jurors’ guilty verdict cannot be considered unanimous when their reasons contradict each other; a dissent by a single appellate judge should preclude her two colleagues from making a finding that must satisfy the “beyond a reasonable doubt” standard; and a precedent laid down by a narrow majority of the Supreme Court Justices should remain open to reconsideration. When truth is important and the cost of error is high, law and epistemology should work in tandem. Our legal system therefore will do well to heed the lessons of epistemology.

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call

Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.