Abstract

Let be the set of recursive functions computable by machines using at most t(x) computation steps on argument x, for all but finitely many inputs x. We call t a name for the complexity class . Suppose we allow our machines to run longer, say h(x, t(x)) steps on argument x, where h is some fixed recursive function. One might expect that, for large enough h, permitting our machines to run longer by an amount h will always allow us to compute new functions, i.e., is a proper subset of . This turns out not to be the case: The “gap theorem” ([2], [3]) implies that for every recursive h there exists a recursive t such that . However, if we restrict our attention to names from a certain subclass of the recursive functions, then we can indeed uniformly increase the size of our -classes. Informally, we call a recursive function t “honest” if some machine computes t(x) in roughly t(x) steps for each argument x. (A precise definition is given in Definition 1 below.) Then according to the “compression theorem” [1], there exists a single recursive function h such that, for every honest t, is a proper subset of . Thus the phenomenon of the gap theorem is avoided by restricting attention to honest functions. It is a surprising consequence of the “honesty theorem” of McCreight and Meyer ([4], [5]) that there is no loss of generality in this restriction. Namely, for any recursive function t there is an honest recursive function t′ such that .

Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call