Abstract

EVO-DEVO’S IDENTITY There is a widespread consensus on the view that evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) is the discipline eventually borne to fill the gap between evolutionary biology and developmental biology, following a divorce between these two fields that extended over more than half a century (Amundson, 2005). On closer inspection, however, this broadly acceptable perspective discloses a wealth of questions, if looked at retrospectively, and of potentially divergent possibilities, if looked at prospectively. The slow pace of integration between the different threads that were converging into evo-devo was well expressed by Raff (2000) in a survey of the main issues in this field. Some 15 years ago Raff, one of the discipline’s founding fathers, remarked that “What constitutes the fundamental problems for a science of evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) depends on whether the scientist is a developmental biologist, a paleontologist or an evolutionary biologist” and drafted a list of at the time hot issues. Evo-devo has answered these questions only in part. However, this discipline is now mature for addressing a number of more precise, and more challenging questions, as I will argue in this article. To date, two sets of problems have been primarily floated in discussions about the identity and research targets of evo-devo. On the one hand are those centered around the (controversial) notions of evolvability, robustness and constraint in connection with the increasing appreciation of the intricacies of the genotype→phenotype map (Alberch, 1991; Altenberg, 1995; West-Eberhard, 2003; Pigliucci, 2010; Wagner and Zhang, 2011). On the other hand are those centered around the notions of origination, innovation, and novelty, the so-called “innovation triad.” To Hendrikse et al. (2007), for example, evolvability is the key issue that justifies recognizing evo-devo as an autonomous discipline. Others, e.g., Muller and Newman (2005), focus instead on the innovation triad. Unfortunately, for all these candidates to core concept of evo-devo, too many alternative definitions have been proposed (or, more dangerously, implicitly assumed), thus adding new items to the dramatically increasing series of biological terms on whose definition there seem to be more and more disagreement. Eventually, we should probably learn to accept that multiple notions associated with each of these terms deserve to be retained and perhaps recognized by adjectival specifications. Similar terminological refinement is applied to other biological terms such as species (e.g., Claridge et al., 1997), homology (e.g., Minelli and Fusco, 2013a), and gene (e.g., Beurton et al., 2000). In discussing the concept of gene in historical perspective, Muller-Wille and Rheinberger (2009) have sensibly recalled Friedrich Nietzsche’s (1887; second essay, para. 13) dictum, that “all concepts in which an entire process is semiotically concentrated elude definition; only that which has no history is definable.” In addition to terminological ambiguity, there is an another problem with the “innovation triad”—the problem that these terms are all framed in terms of “origins.” Framing definitions in terms of origin requires splitting the evolutionary sequence in two contiguous segments, “before” and “after” the origination of a new feature. This splitting is a natural consequence if origination indeed “refers to the specific causality of the generative conditions that underlie both the first origins and the later innovations of phenotypes” and especially “the very first beginnings of phenotypes, e.g., the origin of multicellular assemblies, of complex tissues, and of the generic forms that result from the self-organizational and physical principles of cell interaction (Newman, 1992, 1994). In contrast, innovation [evolutionary modes and mechanisms] and novelty [their phenotypic outcome] designate the processes and results of introducing new characters into already existing phenotypic themes of a certain architecture (bodyplans)” (Muller and Newman, 2005, p. 490). This separation, however, is artificial. The better we know a process, the less we are able to identify its exact origins, these instead being determined by arbitrary choice. In science, and especially in biological disciplines with a strong historical dimension such as evolutionary biology and developmental biology, we should frame questions in terms of transitions rather than origins.

Highlights

  • EVO-DEVO’S IDENTITY There is a widespread consensus on the view that evolutionary developmental biology is the discipline eventually borne to fill the gap between evolutionary biology and developmental biology, following a divorce between these two fields that extended over more than half a century (Amundson, 2005)

  • Some 15 years ago Raff, one of the discipline’s founding fathers, remarked that “What constitutes the fundamental problems for a science of evolutionary developmental biology depends on whether the scientist is a developmental biologist, a paleontologist or an evolutionary biologist” and drafted a list of at the time hot issues

  • Similar terminological refinement is applied to other biological terms such as species (e.g., Claridge et al, 1997), homology (e.g., Minelli and Fusco, 2013a), and gene (e.g., Beurton et al, 2000)

Read more

Summary

Alessandro Minelli *

Analysis in terms of modules (e.g., Raff and Sly, 2000; Schlosser and Wagner, 2004; Callebaut and Rasskin-Gutman, 2005) of the phenotype, and of the developmental processes responsible for it, make the latter notion more attractive to the evo-devoist Most important, this approach in the general case allows the recognition of homologs that do not correspond necessarily to body parts with a distinct topographic and/or functional identity, like wings, fingers, and eyes, i.e., the units the morphologist and the systematist typically choose to base descriptions and comparisons (e.g., Minelli and Fusco, 1995). A set of key questions in evo-devo can be listed in terms of searching for the developmental underpinnings of evolutionary transitions, e.g., transitions from uni- to multicellularity, from direct to indirect development, from unsegmented to segmented body organization All these transitions obviously open the scope for research about parallelism, convergence, and reversal of trends. Besides looking more in detail into this paradigmatic case, it will be worth investigating systematically the distribution of hot points of change along the ontogenetic schedules of other animals and to enquire whether/how this research program can be exported to groups other than metazoans

TWO VERY GREAT CHALLENGES
Findings
Cited in this article after the translation by Ian
Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call