Abstract
Abstract The evidence that we get from peer disagreement is especially problematic from a Bayesian point of view since the belief revision caused by a piece of such evidence cannot be modelled along the lines of Bayesian conditionalisation. This paper explains how exactly this problem arises, what features of peer disagreements are responsible for it, and what lessons should be drawn for both the analysis of peer disagreements and Bayesian conditionalisation as a model of evidence acquisition. In particular, it is pointed out that the same characteristic of evidence from disagreement that explains the problems with Bayesian conditionalisation also suggests an interpretation of suspension of belief in terms of imprecise probabilities.
Highlights
Let us assume that Richard’s credence towards the proposition that Pete will drink more than three beers tonight is 41, while Siena’s credence towards the same proposition is 43
The evidence that we get from peer disagreement is especially problematic from a Bayesian point of view since the belief revision caused by a piece of such evidence cannot be modelled along the lines of Bayesian conditionalisation
This paper explains how exactly this problem arises, what features of peer disagreements are responsible for it, and what lessons should be drawn for both the analysis of peer disagreements and Bayesian conditionalisation as a model of evidence acquisition
Summary
Let us assume that Richard’s credence towards the proposition that Pete will drink more than three beers tonight is 41, while Siena’s credence towards the same proposition is 43. Richard and Siena know Pete’s drinking behaviour well, and they know from past experience that they are good at predicting how many beers he will have. Richard and Siena are epistemic peers concerning Pete’s drinking behaviour: they are competent and knowledgeable with regard to predicting it.. Conciliatory views are often said to apply, when it comes to predicting specific aspects of human behaviour, and in those peer disagreement cases in which we seem unable to find out who is right. In order to tackle these issues, using credence talk is helpful but inessential It is helpful insofar as it simplifies the presentation a lot; it is inessential insofar as all that follows could be reformulated in terms of just three doxastic attitudes – belief, disbelief, and suspension of belief – instead of continuum many.
Talk to us
Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have
Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.