Abstract

Introduction Social scientists and linguists have sometimes written about ‘men's talk’ (Coates, 2003), ‘women's talk’ (Coates, 1996), ‘lesbians’ talk' (Morgan & Wood, 1995) or ‘gay men's talk’ (Leap, 1996) as though the fact that the speakers whose talk is being analysed are men, or women, or gay is sufficient warrant for analysing their talk as such. But, as Schegloff (1997, following Sacks, 1972) has famously pointed out, any given individual can be characterized by a wide range of category terms taken from many different category sets, including, for example, gender, sexuality, political alignment, ethnicity, age, nationality, religion, occupation, place of residence, health status, family position and so on. One consequence of this is that we cannot explain the selection of any given category term simply ‘by saying that they are, after all, such a one’ (Schegloff, 1997: 165). The speaker who is a ‘woman’ is also, for example, a lesbian, a Pagan, an environmentalist, a diabetic, a sister and so on. There is always a range of different characterizations of any one person, all of which are equally ‘true’. Since Schegloff (1997) highlighted the analytical implications of speakers' multiple category memberships, there has been a concerted effort to locate analytic criteria on the basis of which a speaker can legitimately be heard to be speaking as a member of one category rather than another (e.g., Antaki & Widdicombe, 1998; Kitzinger, 2000a; 2006; 2007b; Speer, 2005b; Stokoe, 2005; Wilkinson & Kitzinger, 2003; 2007).

Full Text
Paper version not known

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call