Abstract

INTRODUCTION – AND A FEW CAVEATS The first edition of this volume featured a chapter on political economy by Peter A. Hall (Hall 1997). In it, Hall sought to define political economy by asking the following question: In the subset of those scholars who study the comparative politics of the advanced industrial states, how are political economy explanations constructed? Seen from this vantage, political economy, Hall answered, appears as a field defined by a specific set of concepts; interests, institutions, and ideas within comparative politics. Ten years later, I still find Hall's specification of the boundaries of the field, by reference to this troika of concepts, to be most useful for defining what political economy is and what it is not. However, in replicating Hall's analysis, two caveats are in order. First of all, in following Hall's troika of “interests,” “institutions,” and “ideas” as defining political economy, I necessarily break with this volume's emphasis on “rationality,” “culture,” and “structure” as defining comparative politics. Why then do I prefer Hall's troika of boundary-setting concepts to the one offered by the editors? I do so since taking this route allows me to focus on interests rather than rationality as one of the three defining concepts of the subfield. This positioning is helpful, I suggest, insofar as while many political scientists see rational choice and political economy as synonymous (Weingast and Wittman 2006; Alt and Shepsle 1990), a focus on interests rather than rationality as a core concern allows me to place political economy in a broader frame that engages a more variegated set of literatures, particularly those on institutions and ideas, than would at first blush appear to constitute it.

Full Text
Published version (Free)

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call