Abstract

The term in the United States has more than one reference. Sometimes, refers to the literal and the legal power of the United States in its relationship to other nations and to the world community. We call this sovereignty and contrast it with a second use, which we describe as sovereignty to capture its focus on the relationships among state, federal, and tribal governments within the borders of the United States. The current majority of the United States Supreme Court has revived the language of internal - proffering it as the basis for invalidating or limiting the scope of federal legislation as applied to states. The Court's internal argument is supported in part by characterizing states as bearers of dignitary interests. Neither conceptions of nor of have been static over the centuries. While monarchs once held all and only nobility had democracies today celebrate the of their citizens and the of all persons. Today, equality of persons is central to concepts of popular and personal and human rights law embodies these premises. Further, during the last several decades, collectives of marginalized persons have also asserted rights to recognition and to self-determination of their political authority. The rise of both individual and collective claims of human has constrained sovereignty, for nations can no longer treat human beings with utter disregard by asserting as a defense. Given this nexus between and personhood, the United States Supreme Court's insistence on attributing to states is seen by some as either obnoxious or disingenuous. But the turn to in discussions ought neither to be dismissed nor embraced without puzzling about the work that it, circa 2003, is doing. In this article, we explore the role that the term dignity plays in United States constitutional law by learning when, where, and why the word has been used. That excavation in turn yields several normative insights. First, although concepts of can be identified in constitutional jurisprudence throughout the nation's history, the word was not used in reference to personal constitutional rights by the Supreme Court until the 1940s, in the wake of World War II. During that period, legal and political commentary around the world turned to the term to identify rights of personhood. Thus, talk in the law of the United States is an example of the influence of the norms of other nations, transnational experiences, and international legal treaties and documents on the law of the United States. Second, we argue that the Supreme Court's reinvigoration of doctrines of internal by endowing states with is driven in part by anxiety occasioned by the very permeability of our legal system. Third, both the influences on United States law by international norms and the efforts to ward them off make plain that, given global activity and technology, the law of the United States cannot be secured against external forces. Rather, this country's law is inevitably in conversation (directly or indirectly) with legal developments around the world. Fourth, we believe that as a legal matter, ought not to be reserved exclusively to individuals. Through an analysis of the caselaw of dignity, we have found many examples of the utility of institutional aimed at enabling a fledgling organization - be it a court or a nation - to function. For clarity, we speak of the accorded to nonhumans as role-dignity, by which we mean that is ascribed to an entity to enable it to produce something useful to persons or groups. In contrast, the of people need not be justified in reference to what other goods or effects it produces but rather as something intrinsic in personhood. Fifth, and finally, legal recognition of institutional ought to have a narrower ambit than does recognition of personal dignity. To endorse an entity's claim to role-dignity requires a contextual evaluation of the purposes for which the dignitary claim is made and an assessment of the power of the entity claiming this attribute. In our view, because of revised understandings of the import of human law ought not to rely on institutional role-dignity as a justification for immunizing states from accounting for their behavior. Indeed, being called to account ought not itself be seen as an affront to the role-dignity of an institution but ought, instead, to be understood as one mechanism of acknowledging that entity's power. However, as we detail, this approach does not preclude the use of role-dignity for states to generate other mechanisms to recognize their legitimate authority.

Full Text
Paper version not known

Talk to us

Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have

Schedule a call

Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.