Abstract
In this article, which completes a two-part series on the problem of optimism in Kant’s works, I explore in detail the arguments advanced by the Crusians A. F. Reinhard and D. Weymann against the actual world as the best of all possible worlds and in favour of the actual world as one of the good worlds, Kant’s counterarguments put forward in the mid-1750s drafts and in An Attempt at Some Reflections on Optimism (1759), and further polemical attacks on this topic against Kant by D. Weymann in his works of 1759—1760. I trace the evolution of Kant’s views on optimism from the mid- to the late-1750s, when this concept — once characteristic of the partly unacceptable position that G. W. Leibniz defended in the Theodicy — came to describe Kant’s own views. Leaving aside Voltaire’s resonating works on the Lisbon earthquake, the generic opponent to Kant’s position is an amalgam of Crusians (C. A. Crusius, A. F. Reinhard, D. Weymann, and others), reduced to a caricature with regards to certain theses. I address Weymann’s polemic with Kant to show that, in the pre-critical period, the early Kant advocated beliefs in sphere of practical philosophy that he later radically changed in the critical period, in particular those with regards to freedom and human dignity. The obvious bias of most Kantian scholars against Kant’s opponents prevented researchers from seeing the validity of Weymann’s criticism of Kant for ignoring the problem of freedom. To prove his point, Weymann addressed the difference between the freedom of contradiction (libertas contradictionis) and the freedom of contrariety (libertas contrarietatis). Apparently, Kant himself noticed to a certain degree the validity of Weymann’s criticism, since, after 1759, he abandoned the term “optimism” and, in his later years, distanced himself from his early work An Attempt at Some Reflections on Optimism.
Highlights
В данной статье, завершающей двухчастный цикл о проблеме оптимизма в трудах Канта, подробно разбираются аргументы крузианцев А
A comparison between Alexander Pope (1688—1744) and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646— 1716), which could not have been drawn by Crusius due to obvious reasons, and a comprehensive list of contrary statements made by proponents and opponents of optimism — the latter enjoying Reinhard’s support — add distinctiveness to the essay
Before proceeding to Kant’s invitation to his lectures of 1759, it is necessary to give an overview of his position on optimism, as presented in the rough drafts for the prize-essay competition held by the Berlin Academy of Sciences
Summary
В данной статье, завершающей двухчастный цикл о проблеме оптимизма в трудах Канта, подробно разбираются аргументы крузианцев А. Two series can be equal, even if their parts are in a completely different progression (progression).” The advocates of optimism may find a solution to this problem, Reinhard believes, only in fleeing to the realm of ends, which would suggest the perfection of the actual world They thereby claim that “this system of ends and means, of which the best world consists 1) contains ends worthiest of the perfection of God; 2) that these ends are achieved through the most perfect means; 3) that this occurs at the highest degree of perfection.”. According to Götzen, “the true teaching of the philosophers about the best world is as follows: if God, they say, had wanted to create another thousand worlds, none of them would have as much perfection as the actual world.” In this, the opinion of the philosophers coincides with that of common people: “This is the way the natural man judges!”18 At the same time, Götzen, just like Kant after him, paid little heed to Weymann’s reasoning on freedom. Если бы опровержение стоило затраченных усилий, то я бы, пожалуй, затратил усилия, чтобы понять его» (Hamann, 1955, No 163, S. 425)
Talk to us
Join us for a 30 min session where you can share your feedback and ask us any queries you have
Disclaimer: All third-party content on this website/platform is and will remain the property of their respective owners and is provided on "as is" basis without any warranties, express or implied. Use of third-party content does not indicate any affiliation, sponsorship with or endorsement by them. Any references to third-party content is to identify the corresponding services and shall be considered fair use under The CopyrightLaw.