[MWS 5.1 (2005) 125-130] ISSN 1470-8078 Personal Dilemma or Intellectual Influence? The Relationship between Hannah Arendt and Max Weber* Peter Baehr Tuija Parvikko contends that Weber had a significant impact on Arendt's thought. I suggest that this view is problematic on at least two counts. The first is specific and concerns Arendt's negative attitude towards the ideal type. The second is general: by focusing on a couple of vague family resemblances between the ideas of Weber and Arendt, Dr Parvikko ignores the host of antinomies that are far more conspicuous and signifi cant. In fact, Arendt was anti-Weberian on all vital political axes of her thought. Before I briefly examine these issues, it is worth clarifying Arendt's complex relationship to her mentor Karl Jaspers. Tangled up in blue: Arendt, Jaspers, Weber Tuija Parvikko says that 'Arendt's debt to Weber can best be traced' from her correspondence with Jaspers. 'But alas, it does not tell us anything precise of the dimensions of Weber's thinking that inspired her the most, giving us only a general impression that Jaspers repeatedly encouraged Arendt to read Weber' (p. 236). But that assumes the very point Parvikko wishes to establish: that Arendt was indeed 'inspired' by Weber. A close reading of the Arendt-Jaspers correspondence shows something quite different. It is well known that Jaspers was awe-struck by Weber as both scholar and man of integrity (at least, that is, until he found out about Weber's sexual relationship with Else Jaffé). On numerous instances, he sought to press Weber's ideas on Arendt. How did she respond? Arendt never doubted that Weber was a forceful patriot and a brilliant 'histo rian' . But she faced a dilemma. On the one hand, her political project and reflexes were entirely different from Weber's. So, too, was her ontology, which was phenomenological in the strong sense and a far cry from neo Kantianism. On the other hand, she knew that Jaspers' emotional invest * A Rejoinder to Tuija Parvikko's 'A Note on Max Weber's Impact on Hannah Arendt's Thought', Max Weber Studies 4.2 (July 2004), 235-52.© Max Weber Studies 2005, Department of Applied Social Sciences, London Metropolitan University, Old Castle Street, London El 7NT, UK. 126 Max Weber Studies ment in Weber was beyond negotiation. For Jaspers, Weber was not only a great existentialist thinker. He was also a condensed symbol of that other Germany—patriotic but European, rational, liberal and humane— that had been destroyed with the coming of the Third Reich. Weber, in short, was the embodiment of the true 'German essence'.1 To confront Jaspers on Weber directly, to show that in the areas that most mattered to her Weber's thought was either repugnant or irrelevant, would have strained a friendship that Arendt held dear. She would not risk this. As I have detailed at length elsewhere,2 Arendt had every reason to believe that even the smallest criticism would provoke a volcanic response. Here let me give only one example. In a footnote to chapter 6 of The Human Condition, Arendt observed that 'despite some errors in detail which by now have been corrected', Weber was 'the only historian' to have raised 'with the depth and relevance corresponding to its importance' the impli cations of the loss of the certitudo salutis for modern humanity.3 Arendt was praising Weber. Yet in a letter to her of 1 December, 1960, con gratulating Arendt on the German publication of the Vita Activa, Jaspers homes in on this footnote—and devotes almost half the letter to its impli cations. He is incredulous about Arendt's remarks on Weber's 'errors in detail' and responds: The point is not unimportant to me, because what is involved here is the essence of Max Weber's scholarly achievement. Max Weber may be subject to correction in many other works, if one cares to express it that way, and I have my objections to raise with him, too, as I did during his lifetime. But in this one work (and this is not the case with his other volumes on the sociology of religion) one has...
Read full abstract